Is the Münchhausen trilemma really a trilemma?Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?How can we decide which view to accept concerning our ultimate justification of our knowledge (Münchhausen trilemma)?The coherentist solution to Agrippa’s Trilemma and the possibility of pure/impure justification?Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?Is knowledge really related to propositional modal logic?Relation between an argument and false premise on KnowledgeDoes the second Gettier case really work?Can the correspondence theory of truth really be completely avoided?When taking the axiomatic approach to the Munchausen Trilemma, how do you know something is an axiom?Is Quine's epistemology really just a linguistic reinterpretation of Kant's?Are all Informal Logic really just Formal Logic in disguise?Is evolutionary “morality” really the same thing as human morality?

Unethical behavior : should I report it?

Commercial jet accompanied by small plane near Seattle

Why isn't there a serious attempt at creating a third mass-appeal party in the US?

Why can't my huge trees be chopped down?

What is this spacecraft tethered to another spacecraft in LEO (vintage)

How can religions be structured in ways that allow inter-faith councils to work?

May a man marry the women with whom he committed adultery?

The Sword in the Stone

Correlation length anisotropy in the 2D Ising model

Old French song lyrics with the word "baiser."

Converting 8V AC to 8V DC - bridge rectifier gets very hot while idling

Are the named pipe created by `mknod` and the FIFO created by `mkfifo` equivalent?

Why isn't there any 9.5 digit multimeter or higher?

Where to find an interactive PDF or HTML version of the tex.web documentation?

Japanese reading of an integer

Am I allowed to use personal conversation as a source?

How could Nomadic scholars effectively memorize libraries worth of information

Why is 'n' preferred over "n" for output streams?

What does "see" in "the Holy See" mean?

If Trump gets impeached, how long would Pence be president?

Is it dangerous to add a custom cert authority to a browser?

Word for showing a small part of something briefly to hint to its existence or beauty without fully uncovering it

Why is the number of local variables used in a Java bytecode method not the most economical?

Aftermath of nuclear disaster at Three Mile Island



Is the Münchhausen trilemma really a trilemma?


Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?How can we decide which view to accept concerning our ultimate justification of our knowledge (Münchhausen trilemma)?The coherentist solution to Agrippa’s Trilemma and the possibility of pure/impure justification?Why is the Münchhausen trilemma an unsolved problem?Is knowledge really related to propositional modal logic?Relation between an argument and false premise on KnowledgeDoes the second Gettier case really work?Can the correspondence theory of truth really be completely avoided?When taking the axiomatic approach to the Munchausen Trilemma, how do you know something is an axiom?Is Quine's epistemology really just a linguistic reinterpretation of Kant's?Are all Informal Logic really just Formal Logic in disguise?Is evolutionary “morality” really the same thing as human morality?






.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty margin-bottom:0;








5















It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is its epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question



















  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    Jul 17 at 21:45












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    Jul 17 at 23:27











  • See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

    – J.G.
    Jul 18 at 10:33






  • 1





    It's "its", not "it's".

    – tomasz
    Jul 18 at 12:46






  • 1





    I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

    – Falco
    Jul 18 at 15:36

















5















It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is its epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question



















  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    Jul 17 at 21:45












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    Jul 17 at 23:27











  • See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

    – J.G.
    Jul 18 at 10:33






  • 1





    It's "its", not "it's".

    – tomasz
    Jul 18 at 12:46






  • 1





    I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

    – Falco
    Jul 18 at 15:36













5












5








5


2






It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is its epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?










share|improve this question
















It claims there are three options of which none of them are satisfying.



Circular argument doesn't prove anything because it's just when the premise is the same as the conclusion.



x ∵ x


Infinite Regress isn't clear on why we'd need to do this let alone even possible to implement so it also has no proofs.



x ∵ ... (never ending chain)


Foundationalism is different in that it's actually useful. Mathematics is its epitome. Math has tons of proofs. Math isn't only cohesive but also adhesive. What more do we want?



y ∵ x; where x is presumably true


As for it's criticism: Why start at claim x?



Because presumably, it's either true (via self-evidence or empirical research) or it doesn't matter because sometimes we only want to see where the premise takes us.



Maybe an interesting take on my question is: how do we know it's a trilemma?







epistemology foundationalism






share|improve this question















share|improve this question













share|improve this question




share|improve this question








edited Jul 18 at 16:46







QWERTY_dw

















asked Jul 17 at 20:13









QWERTY_dwQWERTY_dw

3341 gold badge3 silver badges8 bronze badges




3341 gold badge3 silver badges8 bronze badges







  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    Jul 17 at 21:45












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    Jul 17 at 23:27











  • See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

    – J.G.
    Jul 18 at 10:33






  • 1





    It's "its", not "it's".

    – tomasz
    Jul 18 at 12:46






  • 1





    I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

    – Falco
    Jul 18 at 15:36












  • 1





    We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

    – Conifold
    Jul 17 at 21:45












  • As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

    – Cort Ammon
    Jul 17 at 23:27











  • See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

    – J.G.
    Jul 18 at 10:33






  • 1





    It's "its", not "it's".

    – tomasz
    Jul 18 at 12:46






  • 1





    I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

    – Falco
    Jul 18 at 15:36







1




1





We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

– Conifold
Jul 17 at 21:45






We do not need to "really know", it is an argument against those who claim that we can know (typically, foundationalsts), so their premises are accepted for the purposes of reductio. And those are more than enough to make an exhaustive list of alternatives, however it is itemized. Agrippa's version had 5 items instead of 3.

– Conifold
Jul 17 at 21:45














As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

– Cort Ammon
Jul 17 at 23:27





As a consideration... sometimes we don't want to see where the premise takes us. Following a premise takes time and effort. While mathematics may have taken an approach which rewards foundationalism, it can be disconcerting in other disciplines, such as martial arts, where there's a distinct possibility that your entire martial art was founded on an assumption that was wrong. People who arrive at that conclusion often feel like they've wasted 10 or 20 years on an art.

– Cort Ammon
Jul 17 at 23:27













See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

– J.G.
Jul 18 at 10:33





See also philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/7325/…

– J.G.
Jul 18 at 10:33




1




1





It's "its", not "it's".

– tomasz
Jul 18 at 12:46





It's "its", not "it's".

– tomasz
Jul 18 at 12:46




1




1





I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

– Falco
Jul 18 at 15:36





I'd argue that all three forms can support a proof and deliver some value. But none of them is satisfactory, in that none of them is undeniably true, but require some compromise. The first one can prove a theory to be coherent. The second one can prove a theory to be without holes, since it stands on an endless tower of regression. None is really worse than standing on a random assumption.

– Falco
Jul 18 at 15:36










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















9














Circular argument



We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



Infinite regress



You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



Foundational assumptions



We know it's a trilemma.




All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
a little old lady.



"Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
little old lady.



"And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



"That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
turtle."



Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
inadequacies of her position.



"If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
stand on?"



"You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



"But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
patiently.



To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



"It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






share|improve this answer























  • I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

    – Discrete lizard
    Jul 18 at 7:09











  • *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

    – Discrete lizard
    Jul 18 at 7:09












  • @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

    – Cort Ammon
    Jul 18 at 15:26






  • 1





    You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

    – Discrete lizard
    Jul 18 at 16:49






  • 1





    @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

    – Acccumulation
    Jul 18 at 20:58


















6














You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philosophy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, which critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups! Make the circle big and complex enough, and one can do the apparently impossible with it.



If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.



Elaborating on the consequences of the pragmatic re-evaluation of reasoning and rationalism. This involves accepting that truth is not an absolute -- but only "approximately true", and that reasoning is not itself justified, or always valid, hence logic problems such as circularity, or unjustified assumptions, are not fatal problems for a assertion or justification.



Hence flawed justifications, such as the Thomist "5 Proofs" of God -- showing they are not actually "Proofs" does not refute Thomism as a POV. One needs to evaluate its pragmatic effectiveness/value in explaining the world, and the revival of Thomism in recent years shows it is pragmatically useful.



And while Descartes' Foundationalism is actually questionable (there have been challenges on selfhood, much more widely accepted challenges on God, and in particular challenges to the trustworthiness of our reasoning) he still assembled a pretty good foundational case, and much modern thinking is still indebted to him due to the usefulness of his argument.



The cohenrentist response to Munchausen's Trilemma may be logically circular, but the argument that we HAVE to be circular to build a worldview at all, is a highly useful and powerful one anyway.



Similarly, the entire basis of the validity of the scientific/empirical method to attain knowledge is an effectiveness argument -- IE it uses empirical justifications to validate empiricism -- in fairly explicit circularity. Yet science is demonstrably useful, hence the logically invalid justification is -- pragmatically still valid.






share|improve this answer
































    4














    The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



    Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



    Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



    Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



    It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






    share|improve this answer























    • 'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

      – Joshua
      Jul 18 at 19:29







    • 1





      @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

      – Philip Klöcking
      Jul 18 at 19:59











    • I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

      – Joshua
      Jul 18 at 20:03











    • You shouldn't be. ;)

      – Charlie Kilian
      Jul 18 at 20:51











    • @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

      – Philip Klöcking
      Jul 19 at 9:18


















    1














    The first and main point to understand about the trilemma is that it is an argument. As such, its function is to convince other human beings, at least to the extent that they are rational.



    The trilemma is an argument about knowledge and for this reason is often misunderstood as proving the impossibility of any knowledge.



    This, however, is a logical impossibility. Either the Trilemma is itself knowledge or it isn't. It couldn't possibly be knowledge, however, since if it was, it would be a counterexample to its own assertion.



    And if it isn't knowledge, then, why should we care about it?



    We need to care because the Trilemma is effective as a rational argument against a certain idea of science as objective knowledge the physical world.



    Any idea of science as knowledge of the real world which assumes that subjectivity can and should be entirely left out of science is indeed condemned to an infinite regress. And a good theoretical model of this is indeed the theory of Justified True Belief.



    Justified True Belief either leaves you not knowing whether a justified belief is really true, because of the circularity of the theory, or requires that you produce a second-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the initial justification, and then of course to produce a third-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the second-level justification etc., ad infinitum.



    Justified True Belief actually describes quite well the history of science, where each generation of scientists produces a new, more detailed justification without being able to say whether the last science is actual knowledge of the real world.



    The Trilemma is thus effective against any Justified True Belief view of science as knowledge of the real world. It is effective, however, only to the extent that it is a convincing argument. It is still not, and won't ever be, knowledge.



    As a convincing argument, it probably has some effect, up to a point, on how people think about their own practice, scientists in particular.



    However, the fact that it is a convincing argument about the absence of knowledge of the real world, in particular scientific knowledge, doesn't say anything at all as to the possibility of knowledge or indeed about whether we know at least some things or not.



    Suppose you know X. What the Trilemma says is that you cannot justify that you know X. However, what the Trilemma doesn't do, emphatically, is to prove that you don't know X. Again, the Trilemma is not knowledge and therefore isn't knowledge that you don't know X. It is not even an argument that you don't know X. It is only the argument that you cannot "satisfactorily" justify that you know X. So, if you know X, of course you do, and the Trilemma be damned.



    Still, whether you really know X or not is of no interest to anybody but you. What matters to other people is to know themselves whether you know X. However, the Trilemma is this very convincing argument that whatever you will ever say, other people won't be convinced that you know X. And why should they?






    share|improve this answer

























      Your Answer








      StackExchange.ready(function()
      var channelOptions =
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "265"
      ;
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
      createEditor();
      );

      else
      createEditor();

      );

      function createEditor()
      StackExchange.prepareEditor(
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: false,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: null,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader:
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      ,
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      );



      );













      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function ()
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f64638%2fis-the-m%25c3%25bcnchhausen-trilemma-really-a-trilemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');

      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes








      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      9














      Circular argument



      We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



      Infinite regress



      You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



      Foundational assumptions



      We know it's a trilemma.




      All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



      The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



      To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



      I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




      The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
      cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
      a little old lady.



      "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
      earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
      it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
      little old lady.



      "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



      "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
      turtle."



      Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
      the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
      to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
      inadequacies of her position.



      "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
      stand on?"



      "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
      question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
      And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
      larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



      "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
      patiently.



      To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



      "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




      Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



      Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






      share|improve this answer























      • I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09











      • *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09












      • @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

        – Cort Ammon
        Jul 18 at 15:26






      • 1





        You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 16:49






      • 1





        @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

        – Acccumulation
        Jul 18 at 20:58















      9














      Circular argument



      We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



      Infinite regress



      You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



      Foundational assumptions



      We know it's a trilemma.




      All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



      The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



      To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



      I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




      The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
      cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
      a little old lady.



      "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
      earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
      it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
      little old lady.



      "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



      "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
      turtle."



      Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
      the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
      to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
      inadequacies of her position.



      "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
      stand on?"



      "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
      question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
      And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
      larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



      "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
      patiently.



      To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



      "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




      Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



      Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






      share|improve this answer























      • I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09











      • *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09












      • @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

        – Cort Ammon
        Jul 18 at 15:26






      • 1





        You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 16:49






      • 1





        @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

        – Acccumulation
        Jul 18 at 20:58













      9












      9








      9







      Circular argument



      We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



      Infinite regress



      You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



      Foundational assumptions



      We know it's a trilemma.




      All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



      The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



      To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



      I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




      The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
      cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
      a little old lady.



      "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
      earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
      it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
      little old lady.



      "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



      "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
      turtle."



      Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
      the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
      to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
      inadequacies of her position.



      "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
      stand on?"



      "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
      question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
      And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
      larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



      "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
      patiently.



      To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



      "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




      Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



      Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!






      share|improve this answer













      Circular argument



      We know it's a trilemma because the argument is founded on logic and proofs, and all proofs will end in either circular logic, infinite regression, or a foundational assumption.



      Infinite regress



      You can always break a proof into parts. Those parts get simpler and simpler. Keep breaking them up long enough, and all parts will eventually become circular logic, infinite regression, or foundational assumptions.



      Foundational assumptions



      We know it's a trilemma.




      All kidding aside, we find this pattern is generally true. Logical arguments end up in one of these buckets. Sometimes you can change which bucket it ends up in (such as calculus, which permits us to replace some infinite regression arguments like Zeno's paradox with foundational assumptions about how limits behave), but they end up in one of these buckets in the end.



      The main value of the trilemma is to provoke thought. Its to make you think about what must come of rational thought. If it does so, then it has done its job. Proving it "right" however, is more difficult. The whole point of the trilemma is that people who believe in it are not satisfied with the result of any attempt at a proof.



      To prove it, you would have to select what concept of "proof" you wish to explore and what tools you are willing to consider in the proof thereof. Those are rather personal, which means there's not a one size fits all answer, besides the satirical version I wrote above.



      I would argue that you have a clear opinion as to what proofs you find appealing. You appear to find the foundational ones appealing while the others feel like "not an argument." Consider, however, the infamous Turtles argument:




      The following anecdote is told of William James. [...] After a lecture on
      cosmology and the structure of the solar system, James was accosted by
      a little old lady.



      "Your theory that the sun is the centre of the solar system, and the
      earth is a ball which rotates around it has a very convincing ring to
      it, Mr. James, but it's wrong. I've got a better theory," said the
      little old lady.



      "And what is that, madam?" inquired James politely.



      "That we live on a crust of earth which is on the back of a giant
      turtle."



      Not wishing to demolish this absurd little theory by bringing to bear
      the masses of scientific evidence he had at his command, James decided
      to gently dissuade his opponent by making her see some of the
      inadequacies of her position.



      "If your theory is correct, madam," he asked, "what does this turtle
      stand on?"



      "You're a very clever man, Mr. James, and that's a very good
      question," replied the little old lady, "but I have an answer to it.
      And it's this: The first turtle stands on the back of a second, far
      larger, turtle, who stands directly under him."



      "But what does this second turtle stand on?" persisted James
      patiently.



      To this, the little old lady crowed triumphantly,



      "It's no use, Mr. James—it's turtles all the way down."




      Now you don't have to agree with the opinions in this story, but you must admit that there something worth calling a "proof" here, and it ends in infinite regress. As a thought experiment, how would you go about responding to this? Would you be inclined to tell the little old lady that it is not valid to use infinite regression in proofs?



      Consider how we model numbers with Peano arithmetic. We always have an axiom of induction. We may call that simply a foundational axiom, but if we look into why we think it is a valid axiom, it starts to look an aweful lot like an infinite regression argument. We just tucked it away inside a foundational axiom so that we didn't have to worry about it polluting the rest of the proofs. So, perhaps, in a way, such fundamentals of arithemtic simply prove that infinite regress is a valid method of proof in some carefully constructed circumstances!







      share|improve this answer












      share|improve this answer



      share|improve this answer










      answered Jul 17 at 23:43









      Cort AmmonCort Ammon

      15.1k12 silver badges45 bronze badges




      15.1k12 silver badges45 bronze badges












      • I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09











      • *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09












      • @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

        – Cort Ammon
        Jul 18 at 15:26






      • 1





        You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 16:49






      • 1





        @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

        – Acccumulation
        Jul 18 at 20:58

















      • I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09











      • *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 7:09












      • @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

        – Cort Ammon
        Jul 18 at 15:26






      • 1





        You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

        – Discrete lizard
        Jul 18 at 16:49






      • 1





        @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

        – Acccumulation
        Jul 18 at 20:58
















      I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 7:09





      I think the relation between infinite regress and induction is only superficial. If some statement of the natural numbers can be proven by induction, then if you give me a particular natural number*, the proof the statement for this particular number has only a finite number of steps. Can you elaborate how your motivation of induction leads to infinite regress?

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 7:09













      *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 7:09






      *Note that by this I mean a number from some finite subset of the naturals (e.g. a number of which the digits fit in a comment), which is something very different from any natural number. Indeed, to prove the claim for the latter you would need induction... It seems that the circular argument comes closer to my belief in induction.

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 7:09














      @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

      – Cort Ammon
      Jul 18 at 15:26





      @Discretelizard The axiom of induction is itself the infinite regress, just tucked away in an axiom. It says that I can prove that for some function f, f(n) is true for every natural number. Why? Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true, and we'll just use that logic over and over to prove f(n) is true for all n.

      – Cort Ammon
      Jul 18 at 15:26




      1




      1





      You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 16:49





      You write "Because f(0) is true, and if f(0) is true then f(1) is true, and if f(1) is true then f(2) is true, and if f(2) is true then f(3) is true," and this indeed leeds to requiring an infinite number of statements for the full proof. But none of the statements you have written down depends on a statement that has not. In particular, if I pick a number, say 1000, then the method is in fact a valid proof for all numbers up to 1000, without needing induction as an axiom. This is different from the e.g. the turtle example, where we have proven nothing if we stop early.

      – Discrete lizard
      Jul 18 at 16:49




      1




      1





      @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

      – Acccumulation
      Jul 18 at 20:58





      @CortAmmon "if f(0) is true and f(n+1) is true if f(n) is true, then f(n) is true for all real numbers." Induction works only on well-ordered sets, which the set of real numbers is not.

      – Acccumulation
      Jul 18 at 20:58













      6














      You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philosophy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



      Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



      In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



      Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



      However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



      In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



      However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



      If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



      The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, which critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups! Make the circle big and complex enough, and one can do the apparently impossible with it.



      If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.



      Elaborating on the consequences of the pragmatic re-evaluation of reasoning and rationalism. This involves accepting that truth is not an absolute -- but only "approximately true", and that reasoning is not itself justified, or always valid, hence logic problems such as circularity, or unjustified assumptions, are not fatal problems for a assertion or justification.



      Hence flawed justifications, such as the Thomist "5 Proofs" of God -- showing they are not actually "Proofs" does not refute Thomism as a POV. One needs to evaluate its pragmatic effectiveness/value in explaining the world, and the revival of Thomism in recent years shows it is pragmatically useful.



      And while Descartes' Foundationalism is actually questionable (there have been challenges on selfhood, much more widely accepted challenges on God, and in particular challenges to the trustworthiness of our reasoning) he still assembled a pretty good foundational case, and much modern thinking is still indebted to him due to the usefulness of his argument.



      The cohenrentist response to Munchausen's Trilemma may be logically circular, but the argument that we HAVE to be circular to build a worldview at all, is a highly useful and powerful one anyway.



      Similarly, the entire basis of the validity of the scientific/empirical method to attain knowledge is an effectiveness argument -- IE it uses empirical justifications to validate empiricism -- in fairly explicit circularity. Yet science is demonstrably useful, hence the logically invalid justification is -- pragmatically still valid.






      share|improve this answer





























        6














        You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philosophy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



        Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



        In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



        Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



        However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



        In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



        However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



        If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



        The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, which critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups! Make the circle big and complex enough, and one can do the apparently impossible with it.



        If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.



        Elaborating on the consequences of the pragmatic re-evaluation of reasoning and rationalism. This involves accepting that truth is not an absolute -- but only "approximately true", and that reasoning is not itself justified, or always valid, hence logic problems such as circularity, or unjustified assumptions, are not fatal problems for a assertion or justification.



        Hence flawed justifications, such as the Thomist "5 Proofs" of God -- showing they are not actually "Proofs" does not refute Thomism as a POV. One needs to evaluate its pragmatic effectiveness/value in explaining the world, and the revival of Thomism in recent years shows it is pragmatically useful.



        And while Descartes' Foundationalism is actually questionable (there have been challenges on selfhood, much more widely accepted challenges on God, and in particular challenges to the trustworthiness of our reasoning) he still assembled a pretty good foundational case, and much modern thinking is still indebted to him due to the usefulness of his argument.



        The cohenrentist response to Munchausen's Trilemma may be logically circular, but the argument that we HAVE to be circular to build a worldview at all, is a highly useful and powerful one anyway.



        Similarly, the entire basis of the validity of the scientific/empirical method to attain knowledge is an effectiveness argument -- IE it uses empirical justifications to validate empiricism -- in fairly explicit circularity. Yet science is demonstrably useful, hence the logically invalid justification is -- pragmatically still valid.






        share|improve this answer



























          6












          6








          6







          You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philosophy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



          Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



          In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



          Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



          However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



          In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



          However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



          If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



          The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, which critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups! Make the circle big and complex enough, and one can do the apparently impossible with it.



          If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.



          Elaborating on the consequences of the pragmatic re-evaluation of reasoning and rationalism. This involves accepting that truth is not an absolute -- but only "approximately true", and that reasoning is not itself justified, or always valid, hence logic problems such as circularity, or unjustified assumptions, are not fatal problems for a assertion or justification.



          Hence flawed justifications, such as the Thomist "5 Proofs" of God -- showing they are not actually "Proofs" does not refute Thomism as a POV. One needs to evaluate its pragmatic effectiveness/value in explaining the world, and the revival of Thomism in recent years shows it is pragmatically useful.



          And while Descartes' Foundationalism is actually questionable (there have been challenges on selfhood, much more widely accepted challenges on God, and in particular challenges to the trustworthiness of our reasoning) he still assembled a pretty good foundational case, and much modern thinking is still indebted to him due to the usefulness of his argument.



          The cohenrentist response to Munchausen's Trilemma may be logically circular, but the argument that we HAVE to be circular to build a worldview at all, is a highly useful and powerful one anyway.



          Similarly, the entire basis of the validity of the scientific/empirical method to attain knowledge is an effectiveness argument -- IE it uses empirical justifications to validate empiricism -- in fairly explicit circularity. Yet science is demonstrably useful, hence the logically invalid justification is -- pragmatically still valid.






          share|improve this answer















          You have misunderstood the point of the Munchausen Trilemma. It plays a key role in the process of philosophy showing that none of our beliefs are justified knowledge, per the standards of "reasoning".



          Most people hold that they have knowledge and beliefs based on justified reasons, and that beliefs SHOULD be justified, and knowledge isn't knowledge unless it is justified somehow. The term for this is the Principle of Sufficient Reason: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/



          In its first usage, by Spinoza and Leibniz, the PSR basically called for a proof, before one could satisfy it.



          Another key term in the history of knowledge is Justified True Belief -- the criteria that knowledge is only knowledge if one has both justifications, AND it is true. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/



          However, most empiricists since Locke have been indirect realists -- holding that the world is only inferred, not known directly. And if we cannot know the world directly, then one cannot EVER know of a belief about the world is TRUE or not, and JTB is unachievable. https://www.iep.utm.edu/perc-obj/#H2



          In practice today, most "reasoning" people follow a softened version of the PSR -- where "sufficient" reasons are just "supporting justifications are stronger than refutations".



          However, one can apply the Munchausen trilemma to all "supporting justifications" to challenge what THEIR support is. And the answer, in every case, because we cannot complete an infinite series, will lead to and UNJUSTIFIED supposition, or a circular argument.



          If beliefs need to be justified to be reasonably held, then all those justifications, to be held reasonably, must themselves be justified. But they are not and cannot be. The Munchausen Trilemma refutes all claims to be "reasonable" or hold "justified beliefs" based on our current standards of knowledge or reasoning.



          The response among many philosophers has been to embrace larger networks of supporting assumptions, this is the coherence reply to this dilemma. https://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/ The reasoning is that while a simple circle might be a fallacy, a complex web of justifications is not. The name of the Munchausen Trilemma, which critiques the circularity of coherentism, is a ridicule of this claim. Baron von Munchausen cannot pull himself out of the mud, or pull his horse out of the mud, but by pulling on his hair, then lifting himself this way, he was able indirectly to lift his horse through the stirrups! Make the circle big and complex enough, and one can do the apparently impossible with it.



          If no beliefs are justified by our current form of rationality/reasoning, then philosophy and knowledge must both become non-rationalist. The response to this has varied between Europe and the US. In Europe, it has been an embrace of radical relativity -- IE postmodernism. In the US it has typically lead to pragmatism, where one can justify beliefs based on the pragmatic criteria of their utility/effectiveness.



          Elaborating on the consequences of the pragmatic re-evaluation of reasoning and rationalism. This involves accepting that truth is not an absolute -- but only "approximately true", and that reasoning is not itself justified, or always valid, hence logic problems such as circularity, or unjustified assumptions, are not fatal problems for a assertion or justification.



          Hence flawed justifications, such as the Thomist "5 Proofs" of God -- showing they are not actually "Proofs" does not refute Thomism as a POV. One needs to evaluate its pragmatic effectiveness/value in explaining the world, and the revival of Thomism in recent years shows it is pragmatically useful.



          And while Descartes' Foundationalism is actually questionable (there have been challenges on selfhood, much more widely accepted challenges on God, and in particular challenges to the trustworthiness of our reasoning) he still assembled a pretty good foundational case, and much modern thinking is still indebted to him due to the usefulness of his argument.



          The cohenrentist response to Munchausen's Trilemma may be logically circular, but the argument that we HAVE to be circular to build a worldview at all, is a highly useful and powerful one anyway.



          Similarly, the entire basis of the validity of the scientific/empirical method to attain knowledge is an effectiveness argument -- IE it uses empirical justifications to validate empiricism -- in fairly explicit circularity. Yet science is demonstrably useful, hence the logically invalid justification is -- pragmatically still valid.







          share|improve this answer














          share|improve this answer



          share|improve this answer








          edited Jul 19 at 17:40

























          answered Jul 18 at 0:12









          DcleveDcleve

          1,4921 gold badge3 silver badges20 bronze badges




          1,4921 gold badge3 silver badges20 bronze badges





















              4














              The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



              Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



              Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



              Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



              It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






              share|improve this answer























              • 'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 19:29







              • 1





                @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 18 at 19:59











              • I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 20:03











              • You shouldn't be. ;)

                – Charlie Kilian
                Jul 18 at 20:51











              • @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 19 at 9:18















              4














              The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



              Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



              Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



              Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



              It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






              share|improve this answer























              • 'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 19:29







              • 1





                @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 18 at 19:59











              • I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 20:03











              • You shouldn't be. ;)

                – Charlie Kilian
                Jul 18 at 20:51











              • @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 19 at 9:18













              4












              4








              4







              The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



              Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



              Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



              Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



              It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.






              share|improve this answer













              The trilemma is about justification of a given proposition. Any justification, so the story goes, takes ultimately one of these forms if faced with skepticism.



              Therefore, the third option is about people who answer to the question "But how do you know that x really is true" dogmatically, e.g. with "Because it is", "Because I say so", etc.



              Ultimately, the answers "It is self-evident" and "Empirical research shows it" are, if taken as an end-point of justification, arbitrary since the skeptical objections "Why do you assume self-evidence here, I do not follow" and "What are the standards of this research, why should this be a particularly good standard for the truth of the proposition" are still valid.



              Sure, we accept that for statements about the world, empirical research is probably the gold standard and brings us as close to the truth as we might get, but that's not the setting in which the trilemma is supposed to work.



              It is about forms of justification, and ending the chain of justification at an arbitrary point is dogmatic, no matter how well-justified the point itself might be. If I claim that this justification was unquestionable and ultimately justifies the whole chain as true, I am dogmatic.







              share|improve this answer












              share|improve this answer



              share|improve this answer










              answered Jul 17 at 22:10









              Philip KlöckingPhilip Klöcking

              7,8052 gold badges27 silver badges54 bronze badges




              7,8052 gold badges27 silver badges54 bronze badges












              • 'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 19:29







              • 1





                @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 18 at 19:59











              • I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 20:03











              • You shouldn't be. ;)

                – Charlie Kilian
                Jul 18 at 20:51











              • @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 19 at 9:18

















              • 'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 19:29







              • 1





                @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 18 at 19:59











              • I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

                – Joshua
                Jul 18 at 20:03











              • You shouldn't be. ;)

                – Charlie Kilian
                Jul 18 at 20:51











              • @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

                – Philip Klöcking
                Jul 19 at 9:18
















              'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

              – Joshua
              Jul 18 at 19:29






              'We know nothing' is an untenable proposition though.

              – Joshua
              Jul 18 at 19:29





              1




              1





              @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

              – Philip Klöcking
              Jul 18 at 19:59





              @Joshua And nobody ever claimed as much, nor is the trilemma. This is all about apodictic certainty and how any justification of such would run into these forms. The Münchhausen Trilemma objects against logical necessity, not pragmatic reasonability.

              – Philip Klöcking
              Jul 18 at 19:59













              I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

              – Joshua
              Jul 18 at 20:03





              I am absolutely certain of your existence as well as mine.

              – Joshua
              Jul 18 at 20:03













              You shouldn't be. ;)

              – Charlie Kilian
              Jul 18 at 20:51





              You shouldn't be. ;)

              – Charlie Kilian
              Jul 18 at 20:51













              @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

              – Philip Klöcking
              Jul 19 at 9:18





              @Joshua See, the question is not about your conviction, but your justification thereof. Thus, you can be absolutely certain of whatever you want, as long as you do not or cannot further justify this conviction, you effectively fall under the third case.

              – Philip Klöcking
              Jul 19 at 9:18











              1














              The first and main point to understand about the trilemma is that it is an argument. As such, its function is to convince other human beings, at least to the extent that they are rational.



              The trilemma is an argument about knowledge and for this reason is often misunderstood as proving the impossibility of any knowledge.



              This, however, is a logical impossibility. Either the Trilemma is itself knowledge or it isn't. It couldn't possibly be knowledge, however, since if it was, it would be a counterexample to its own assertion.



              And if it isn't knowledge, then, why should we care about it?



              We need to care because the Trilemma is effective as a rational argument against a certain idea of science as objective knowledge the physical world.



              Any idea of science as knowledge of the real world which assumes that subjectivity can and should be entirely left out of science is indeed condemned to an infinite regress. And a good theoretical model of this is indeed the theory of Justified True Belief.



              Justified True Belief either leaves you not knowing whether a justified belief is really true, because of the circularity of the theory, or requires that you produce a second-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the initial justification, and then of course to produce a third-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the second-level justification etc., ad infinitum.



              Justified True Belief actually describes quite well the history of science, where each generation of scientists produces a new, more detailed justification without being able to say whether the last science is actual knowledge of the real world.



              The Trilemma is thus effective against any Justified True Belief view of science as knowledge of the real world. It is effective, however, only to the extent that it is a convincing argument. It is still not, and won't ever be, knowledge.



              As a convincing argument, it probably has some effect, up to a point, on how people think about their own practice, scientists in particular.



              However, the fact that it is a convincing argument about the absence of knowledge of the real world, in particular scientific knowledge, doesn't say anything at all as to the possibility of knowledge or indeed about whether we know at least some things or not.



              Suppose you know X. What the Trilemma says is that you cannot justify that you know X. However, what the Trilemma doesn't do, emphatically, is to prove that you don't know X. Again, the Trilemma is not knowledge and therefore isn't knowledge that you don't know X. It is not even an argument that you don't know X. It is only the argument that you cannot "satisfactorily" justify that you know X. So, if you know X, of course you do, and the Trilemma be damned.



              Still, whether you really know X or not is of no interest to anybody but you. What matters to other people is to know themselves whether you know X. However, the Trilemma is this very convincing argument that whatever you will ever say, other people won't be convinced that you know X. And why should they?






              share|improve this answer



























                1














                The first and main point to understand about the trilemma is that it is an argument. As such, its function is to convince other human beings, at least to the extent that they are rational.



                The trilemma is an argument about knowledge and for this reason is often misunderstood as proving the impossibility of any knowledge.



                This, however, is a logical impossibility. Either the Trilemma is itself knowledge or it isn't. It couldn't possibly be knowledge, however, since if it was, it would be a counterexample to its own assertion.



                And if it isn't knowledge, then, why should we care about it?



                We need to care because the Trilemma is effective as a rational argument against a certain idea of science as objective knowledge the physical world.



                Any idea of science as knowledge of the real world which assumes that subjectivity can and should be entirely left out of science is indeed condemned to an infinite regress. And a good theoretical model of this is indeed the theory of Justified True Belief.



                Justified True Belief either leaves you not knowing whether a justified belief is really true, because of the circularity of the theory, or requires that you produce a second-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the initial justification, and then of course to produce a third-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the second-level justification etc., ad infinitum.



                Justified True Belief actually describes quite well the history of science, where each generation of scientists produces a new, more detailed justification without being able to say whether the last science is actual knowledge of the real world.



                The Trilemma is thus effective against any Justified True Belief view of science as knowledge of the real world. It is effective, however, only to the extent that it is a convincing argument. It is still not, and won't ever be, knowledge.



                As a convincing argument, it probably has some effect, up to a point, on how people think about their own practice, scientists in particular.



                However, the fact that it is a convincing argument about the absence of knowledge of the real world, in particular scientific knowledge, doesn't say anything at all as to the possibility of knowledge or indeed about whether we know at least some things or not.



                Suppose you know X. What the Trilemma says is that you cannot justify that you know X. However, what the Trilemma doesn't do, emphatically, is to prove that you don't know X. Again, the Trilemma is not knowledge and therefore isn't knowledge that you don't know X. It is not even an argument that you don't know X. It is only the argument that you cannot "satisfactorily" justify that you know X. So, if you know X, of course you do, and the Trilemma be damned.



                Still, whether you really know X or not is of no interest to anybody but you. What matters to other people is to know themselves whether you know X. However, the Trilemma is this very convincing argument that whatever you will ever say, other people won't be convinced that you know X. And why should they?






                share|improve this answer

























                  1












                  1








                  1







                  The first and main point to understand about the trilemma is that it is an argument. As such, its function is to convince other human beings, at least to the extent that they are rational.



                  The trilemma is an argument about knowledge and for this reason is often misunderstood as proving the impossibility of any knowledge.



                  This, however, is a logical impossibility. Either the Trilemma is itself knowledge or it isn't. It couldn't possibly be knowledge, however, since if it was, it would be a counterexample to its own assertion.



                  And if it isn't knowledge, then, why should we care about it?



                  We need to care because the Trilemma is effective as a rational argument against a certain idea of science as objective knowledge the physical world.



                  Any idea of science as knowledge of the real world which assumes that subjectivity can and should be entirely left out of science is indeed condemned to an infinite regress. And a good theoretical model of this is indeed the theory of Justified True Belief.



                  Justified True Belief either leaves you not knowing whether a justified belief is really true, because of the circularity of the theory, or requires that you produce a second-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the initial justification, and then of course to produce a third-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the second-level justification etc., ad infinitum.



                  Justified True Belief actually describes quite well the history of science, where each generation of scientists produces a new, more detailed justification without being able to say whether the last science is actual knowledge of the real world.



                  The Trilemma is thus effective against any Justified True Belief view of science as knowledge of the real world. It is effective, however, only to the extent that it is a convincing argument. It is still not, and won't ever be, knowledge.



                  As a convincing argument, it probably has some effect, up to a point, on how people think about their own practice, scientists in particular.



                  However, the fact that it is a convincing argument about the absence of knowledge of the real world, in particular scientific knowledge, doesn't say anything at all as to the possibility of knowledge or indeed about whether we know at least some things or not.



                  Suppose you know X. What the Trilemma says is that you cannot justify that you know X. However, what the Trilemma doesn't do, emphatically, is to prove that you don't know X. Again, the Trilemma is not knowledge and therefore isn't knowledge that you don't know X. It is not even an argument that you don't know X. It is only the argument that you cannot "satisfactorily" justify that you know X. So, if you know X, of course you do, and the Trilemma be damned.



                  Still, whether you really know X or not is of no interest to anybody but you. What matters to other people is to know themselves whether you know X. However, the Trilemma is this very convincing argument that whatever you will ever say, other people won't be convinced that you know X. And why should they?






                  share|improve this answer













                  The first and main point to understand about the trilemma is that it is an argument. As such, its function is to convince other human beings, at least to the extent that they are rational.



                  The trilemma is an argument about knowledge and for this reason is often misunderstood as proving the impossibility of any knowledge.



                  This, however, is a logical impossibility. Either the Trilemma is itself knowledge or it isn't. It couldn't possibly be knowledge, however, since if it was, it would be a counterexample to its own assertion.



                  And if it isn't knowledge, then, why should we care about it?



                  We need to care because the Trilemma is effective as a rational argument against a certain idea of science as objective knowledge the physical world.



                  Any idea of science as knowledge of the real world which assumes that subjectivity can and should be entirely left out of science is indeed condemned to an infinite regress. And a good theoretical model of this is indeed the theory of Justified True Belief.



                  Justified True Belief either leaves you not knowing whether a justified belief is really true, because of the circularity of the theory, or requires that you produce a second-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the initial justification, and then of course to produce a third-level justification to justify all the elements coming into the second-level justification etc., ad infinitum.



                  Justified True Belief actually describes quite well the history of science, where each generation of scientists produces a new, more detailed justification without being able to say whether the last science is actual knowledge of the real world.



                  The Trilemma is thus effective against any Justified True Belief view of science as knowledge of the real world. It is effective, however, only to the extent that it is a convincing argument. It is still not, and won't ever be, knowledge.



                  As a convincing argument, it probably has some effect, up to a point, on how people think about their own practice, scientists in particular.



                  However, the fact that it is a convincing argument about the absence of knowledge of the real world, in particular scientific knowledge, doesn't say anything at all as to the possibility of knowledge or indeed about whether we know at least some things or not.



                  Suppose you know X. What the Trilemma says is that you cannot justify that you know X. However, what the Trilemma doesn't do, emphatically, is to prove that you don't know X. Again, the Trilemma is not knowledge and therefore isn't knowledge that you don't know X. It is not even an argument that you don't know X. It is only the argument that you cannot "satisfactorily" justify that you know X. So, if you know X, of course you do, and the Trilemma be damned.



                  Still, whether you really know X or not is of no interest to anybody but you. What matters to other people is to know themselves whether you know X. However, the Trilemma is this very convincing argument that whatever you will ever say, other people won't be convinced that you know X. And why should they?







                  share|improve this answer












                  share|improve this answer



                  share|improve this answer










                  answered Jul 18 at 10:23









                  SpeakpigeonSpeakpigeon

                  6452 silver badges10 bronze badges




                  6452 silver badges10 bronze badges



























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded
















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Philosophy Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid


                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function ()
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f64638%2fis-the-m%25c3%25bcnchhausen-trilemma-really-a-trilemma%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Category:9 (number) SubcategoriesMedia in category "9 (number)"Navigation menuUpload mediaGND ID: 4485639-8Library of Congress authority ID: sh85091979ReasonatorScholiaStatistics

                      Circuit construction for execution of conditional statements using least significant bitHow are two different registers being used as “control”?How exactly is the stated composite state of the two registers being produced using the $R_zz$ controlled rotations?Efficiently performing controlled rotations in HHLWould this quantum algorithm implementation work?How to prepare a superposed states of odd integers from $1$ to $sqrtN$?Why is this implementation of the order finding algorithm not working?Circuit construction for Hamiltonian simulationHow can I invert the least significant bit of a certain term of a superposed state?Implementing an oracleImplementing a controlled sum operation

                      Magento 2 “No Payment Methods” in Admin New OrderHow to integrate Paypal Express Checkout with the Magento APIMagento 1.5 - Sales > Order > edit order and shipping methods disappearAuto Invoice Check/Money Order Payment methodAdd more simple payment methods?Shipping methods not showingWhat should I do to change payment methods if changing the configuration has no effects?1.9 - No Payment Methods showing upMy Payment Methods not Showing for downloadable/virtual product when checkout?Magento2 API to access internal payment methodHow to call an existing payment methods in the registration form?