If 'B is more likely given A', then 'A is more likely given B' Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)What is a very intuitive way to teach the Bayes formula to undergraduates?Why does “explaining away” make intuitive sense?What is the intuition behind (M)ANCOVA and when/why should one use it?An example of r.v.s such that their distribution has more (conditional) independencies than their directed graphical modelIntuition for “weights” in simple linear regressionIntuitive explanation of the F-statistic formula?the intuition behind that the variance of increment for Brownian Motion is time intervalWhy is it that when the score variance gets LARGER we get MORE confident about the MLE estimate?Conditional probability question - given pdfIntuition behind infinite CRLBWhy do parametric models learn more slowly by design?

Can melee weapons be used to deliver Contact Poisons?

Compare a given version number in the form major.minor.build.patch and see if one is less than the other

Do I really need to have a message in a novel to appeal to readers?

8 Prisoners wearing hats

old style "caution" boxes

How would a mousetrap for use in space work?

Why didn't Eitri join the fight?

If a VARCHAR(MAX) column is included in an index, is the entire value always stored in the index page(s)?

When a candle burns, why does the top of wick glow if bottom of flame is hottest?

An adverb for when you're not exaggerating

Is safe to use va_start macro with this as parameter?

What does "lightly crushed" mean for cardamon pods?

How to answer "Have you ever been terminated?"

Why are both D and D# fitting into my E minor key?

How do I find out the mythology and history of my Fortress?

How to find all the available tools in mac terminal?

Did MS DOS itself ever use blinking text?

Most bit efficient text communication method?

How does the math work when buying airline miles?

If my PI received research grants from a company to be able to pay my postdoc salary, did I have a potential conflict interest too?

Can anything be seen from the center of the Boötes void? How dark would it be?

Is "Reachable Object" really an NP-complete problem?

When the Haste spell ends on a creature, do attackers have advantage against that creature?

Irreducible of finite Krull dimension implies quasi-compact?



If 'B is more likely given A', then 'A is more likely given B'



Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern)What is a very intuitive way to teach the Bayes formula to undergraduates?Why does “explaining away” make intuitive sense?What is the intuition behind (M)ANCOVA and when/why should one use it?An example of r.v.s such that their distribution has more (conditional) independencies than their directed graphical modelIntuition for “weights” in simple linear regressionIntuitive explanation of the F-statistic formula?the intuition behind that the variance of increment for Brownian Motion is time intervalWhy is it that when the score variance gets LARGER we get MORE confident about the MLE estimate?Conditional probability question - given pdfIntuition behind infinite CRLBWhy do parametric models learn more slowly by design?



.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty margin-bottom:0;








8












$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago


















8












$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago














8












8








8


3



$begingroup$


I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I am trying to get a clearer intuition behind: "If $A$ makes $B$ more likely then $B$ makes $A$ more likely" i.e




Let $n(S)$ denote the size of the space in which $A$ and $B$ are, then



Claim: $P(B|A)>P(B)$ so $n(AB)/n(A) > n(B)/n(S)$



so $n(AB)/n(B) > n(A)/n(S)$



which is $P(A|B)>P(A)$




I understand the math, but why does this make intuitive sense?







probability inference conditional-probability intuition association-measure






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited 2 days ago









Martijn Weterings

14.8k2164




14.8k2164










asked Apr 14 at 6:54









Rahul DeoraRahul Deora

12719




12719







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago













  • 1




    $begingroup$
    I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
    $endgroup$
    – Martijn Weterings
    2 days ago








1




1




$begingroup$
I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
2 days ago





$begingroup$
I edited the question to removed the word 'make'. This question sounded a bit like those ambiguous questions on Facebook, those where you have to solve some algebraic sum with pictures and people get widely different answers due to different interpretations of the question. That is not something we want here. (an alternative is to close the question for being unclear and have the OP change it).
$endgroup$
– Martijn Weterings
2 days ago











13 Answers
13






active

oldest

votes


















9












$begingroup$

By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






share|cite|improve this answer










New contributor




Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
    $endgroup$
    – Pod
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
    $endgroup$
    – Rahul Deora
    2 days ago






  • 4




    $begingroup$
    Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
    $endgroup$
    – Richard Hardy
    yesterday










  • $begingroup$
    @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
    $endgroup$
    – Peter A. Schneider
    yesterday


















19












$begingroup$

I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



Bayes' rule:
$$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



$$fracP(AP(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



Then $fracP(AP(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
    $endgroup$
    – probabilityislogic
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
    $endgroup$
    – Acccumulation
    2 days ago










  • $begingroup$
    A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
    $endgroup$
    – Ray
    2 days ago



















11












$begingroup$

Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



And so on.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$








  • 4




    $begingroup$
    That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    Apr 14 at 14:09






  • 6




    $begingroup$
    @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
    $endgroup$
    – hobbs
    Apr 14 at 16:27






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
    $endgroup$
    – hobbs
    Apr 14 at 16:29






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    Apr 14 at 21:04






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter Flom
    Apr 14 at 21:34


















9












$begingroup$

To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
$$
eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
$$

so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$




















    2












    $begingroup$

    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$








    • 1




      $begingroup$
      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
      $endgroup$
      – mdewey
      Apr 14 at 11:16






    • 2




      $begingroup$
      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
      $endgroup$
      – Dasherman
      Apr 14 at 12:24



















    2












    $begingroup$

    If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$




















      2












      $begingroup$

      You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



      $beginarraycc
      beginarraycc
      && A & lnot A & \
      &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
      B& a+b& a & b \
      lnot B & c+d& c & d \
      endarray
      endarray$



      • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
        beginarraycc
        && A & lnot A & \
        &1 & x & 1-x \hline
        B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
        lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
        endarray
        endarray$$
        In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



      • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
        beginarraycc
        && A & lnot A & \
        &1 & x & 1-x \hline
        B& y& a+z & b-z \
        lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
        endarray
        endarray$$



        You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



        Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



      So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



      If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$




















        2












        $begingroup$

        Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



        $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



        Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



        $$Delta(A|B)
        = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
        = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
        = fracmathbbP(BmathbbP(B)
        = Delta(B|A).$$



        The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




        $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$




















          1












          $begingroup$

          You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



          You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
            $endgroup$
            – Martijn Weterings
            Apr 14 at 19:09



















          1












          $begingroup$

          It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



          • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

          The following is not true:



          • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

          • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

          However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



          • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

          The following is true:



          • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

          • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

          If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



          1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

          2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

          Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



          Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



          Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



          Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



          If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



          However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



          Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



          As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






          share|cite|improve this answer










          New contributor




          H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
          Check out our Code of Conduct.






          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            2 days ago











          • $begingroup$
            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
            $endgroup$
            – H4uZ
            2 days ago


















          0












          $begingroup$

          There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



          Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



          If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$








          • 5




            $begingroup$
            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
            $endgroup$
            – wizzwizz4
            Apr 14 at 14:31



















          0












          $begingroup$

          The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




          If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




          Implication:
          A true -> B true
          A false -> B true or false
          Reverse implication:
          B true -> A true or false
          B false -> A false


          Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




          If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




          Weak implication:
          A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
          A false -> B true or false
          Reverse weak implication:
          B true -> A true or false
          B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





          share|cite|improve this answer








          New contributor




          Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
          Check out our Code of Conduct.






          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            2 days ago










          • $begingroup$
            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
            $endgroup$
            – Rainer P.
            2 days ago










          • $begingroup$
            A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
            $endgroup$
            – Martijn Weterings
            yesterday


















          0












          $begingroup$

          Suppose Alice has a higher free throw rate than average. Then the probability of a shot being successful, given that it's attempted by Alice, is greater than the probability of a shot being successful in general $P(successful|Alice)>P(successful)$. We can also conclude that Alice's share of successful shots is greater than her share of shots in general: $P(Alice|successful)>P(Alice)$.



          Or suppose there's a school that has 10% of the students in its school district, but 15% of the straight-A students. Then clearly the percentage of students at that school who are straight-A students is higher than the district-wide percentage.



          Another way of looking at it: A is more likely, given B, if $P(A&B)>P(A)P(B)$, and that is completely symmetrical with respect to $A$ and $B$.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$











            protected by gung 2 days ago



            Thank you for your interest in this question.
            Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



            Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?














            13 Answers
            13






            active

            oldest

            votes








            13 Answers
            13






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes









            9












            $begingroup$

            By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



            Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



            What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



            In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



            Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



            So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



            What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



            One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

            Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



            Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






            share|cite|improve this answer










            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.






            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
              $endgroup$
              – Pod
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
              $endgroup$
              – Rahul Deora
              2 days ago






            • 4




              $begingroup$
              Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
              $endgroup$
              – Richard Hardy
              yesterday










            • $begingroup$
              @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
              $endgroup$
              – Peter A. Schneider
              yesterday















            9












            $begingroup$

            By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



            Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



            What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



            In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



            Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



            So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



            What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



            One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

            Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



            Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






            share|cite|improve this answer










            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.






            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
              $endgroup$
              – Pod
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
              $endgroup$
              – Rahul Deora
              2 days ago






            • 4




              $begingroup$
              Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
              $endgroup$
              – Richard Hardy
              yesterday










            • $begingroup$
              @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
              $endgroup$
              – Peter A. Schneider
              yesterday













            9












            9








            9





            $begingroup$

            By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



            Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



            What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



            In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



            Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



            So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



            What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



            One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

            Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



            Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.






            share|cite|improve this answer










            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.






            $endgroup$



            By way of intuition, real world examples such as Peter Flom gives are most helpful for some people. The other thing that commonly helps people is pictures. So, to cover most bases, let's have some pictures.



            Conditional probability diagram showing independenceConditional probability diagram showing dependence



            What we have here are two very basic diagrams showing probabilities. The first shows two independent predicates I'll call Red and Plain. It is clear that they are independent because the lines line up. The proportion of plain area that is red is the same as the proportion of stripy area that is red and is also the same as the total proportion that is red.



            In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have expanded some of the plain red area into the stripy area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely.



            Meanwhile, have a look at the plain side of that image. Clearly the proportion of the plain region that is red is greater than the proportion of the whole image that is red. That is because the plain region has been given a bunch more area and all of it is red.



            So, red makes plain more likely, and plain makes red more likely.



            What's actually happening here? A is evidence for B (that is, A makes B more likely) when the area that contains both A and B is bigger than would be predicted if they were independent. Because the intersection between A and B is the same as the intersection between B and A, that also implies that B is evidence for A.



            One note of caution: although the argument above seems very symmetrical, it may not be the case that the strength of evidence in both directions is equal. For example, consider this third image. Conditional probability diagram showing extreme dependence

            Here the same thing has happened: plain red has eaten up territory previously belonging to stripy red. In fact, it has completely finished the job!



            Note that the point being red outright guarantees plainness because there are no stripy red regions left. However a point being plain has not guaranteed redness, because there are still green regions left. Nevertheless, a point in the box being plain increases the chance that it is red, and a point being red increases the chance that it is plain. Both directions imply more likely, just not by the same amount.







            share|cite|improve this answer










            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.









            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited 2 days ago





















            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.









            answered Apr 14 at 20:22









            JosiahJosiah

            2144




            2144




            New contributor




            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.





            New contributor





            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.






            Josiah is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
            Check out our Code of Conduct.











            • $begingroup$
              I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
              $endgroup$
              – Pod
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
              $endgroup$
              – Rahul Deora
              2 days ago






            • 4




              $begingroup$
              Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
              $endgroup$
              – Richard Hardy
              yesterday










            • $begingroup$
              @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
              $endgroup$
              – Peter A. Schneider
              yesterday
















            • $begingroup$
              I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
              $endgroup$
              – Pod
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
              $endgroup$
              – Rahul Deora
              2 days ago






            • 4




              $begingroup$
              Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
              $endgroup$
              – Richard Hardy
              yesterday










            • $begingroup$
              @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
              $endgroup$
              – Peter A. Schneider
              yesterday















            $begingroup$
            I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
            $endgroup$
            – Pod
            2 days ago




            $begingroup$
            I like the images :) However It looks like either the images or the explanation is flipped: In the second image, we have non-independent distributions. Specifically, we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area without changing the fact that it is red. Clearly then, being red makes being plain more likely. -- your second image has gained plain area than the first, so going from image 1 to 2 we have moved plain area into the striped area.
            $endgroup$
            – Pod
            2 days ago












            $begingroup$
            So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            2 days ago




            $begingroup$
            So, if I have venn diagram with some common A,B intersection area and all I do is increase that intersection area, I automatically add more A,B for the entire space(without making the space larger) and change/increase n(A)/n(S) and n(B)/n(S) as a consequence. Right? More comments?
            $endgroup$
            – Rahul Deora
            2 days ago




            4




            4




            $begingroup$
            Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
            $endgroup$
            – Richard Hardy
            yesterday




            $begingroup$
            Red vs. green is a problematic combination for color blind people.
            $endgroup$
            – Richard Hardy
            yesterday












            $begingroup$
            @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
            $endgroup$
            – Peter A. Schneider
            yesterday




            $begingroup$
            @Pod I think it's a natural language ambiguity you are describing. Read "we have moved some of the stripy red area into the plain area" as "we have moved some of the area formerly known as stripy red and changed it into the plain area". I think you [mis-]read it as "we have expanded some of the stripy red area into the area formerly known as plain".
            $endgroup$
            – Peter A. Schneider
            yesterday













            19












            $begingroup$

            I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



            Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



            Bayes' rule:
            $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



            assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



            $$fracP(AP(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



            If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



            Then $fracP(AP(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



            This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
              $endgroup$
              – probabilityislogic
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
              $endgroup$
              – Acccumulation
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
              $endgroup$
              – Ray
              2 days ago
















            19












            $begingroup$

            I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



            Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



            Bayes' rule:
            $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



            assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



            $$fracP(AP(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



            If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



            Then $fracP(AP(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



            This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
              $endgroup$
              – probabilityislogic
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
              $endgroup$
              – Acccumulation
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
              $endgroup$
              – Ray
              2 days ago














            19












            19








            19





            $begingroup$

            I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



            Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



            Bayes' rule:
            $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



            assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



            $$fracP(AP(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



            If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



            Then $fracP(AP(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



            This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$



            I think another mathematical way of putting it may help. Consider the claim in the context of Bayes' rule:



            Claim: if $P(B|A)>P(B)$ then $P(A|B) > P(A)$



            Bayes' rule:
            $$ P(A mid B) = fracP(B mid A) , P(A)P(B) $$



            assuming $P(B)$ nonzero. Thus



            $$fracP(AP(A) = fracP(BP(B)$$



            If $P(B|A)>P(B)$, then $fracP(BP(B) > 1$.



            Then $fracP(AP(A) > 1$, and so $P(A|B) > P(A)$.



            This proves the claim and an even stronger conclusion - that the respective proportions of the likelihoods must be equal.







            share|cite|improve this answer














            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited Apr 14 at 18:17

























            answered Apr 14 at 16:19









            Aaron HallAaron Hall

            388215




            388215











            • $begingroup$
              I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
              $endgroup$
              – probabilityislogic
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
              $endgroup$
              – Acccumulation
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
              $endgroup$
              – Ray
              2 days ago

















            • $begingroup$
              I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
              $endgroup$
              – probabilityislogic
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
              $endgroup$
              – Acccumulation
              2 days ago










            • $begingroup$
              A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
              $endgroup$
              – Ray
              2 days ago
















            $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            2 days ago




            $begingroup$
            I liked this because it shows the stronger link "if A makes B x percent more likely, then B makes A x percent more likely"
            $endgroup$
            – probabilityislogic
            2 days ago












            $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            2 days ago




            $begingroup$
            @probabilityislogic Phrasing it that way introduces ambiguity. If the prior probability is 10%, and the posterior is 15%, did the probability increase 5% (15% minus 10%) or 50% (15% divided by 10%)?
            $endgroup$
            – Acccumulation
            2 days ago












            $begingroup$
            A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
            $endgroup$
            – Ray
            2 days ago





            $begingroup$
            A simpler proof: If $P(B|A) > P(B)$, then using that and Bayes' Rule, we have $P(A|B) = P(B|A)P(A)/P(B) > P(B)P(A)/P(B) = P(A)$
            $endgroup$
            – Ray
            2 days ago












            11












            $begingroup$

            Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



            But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



            If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

            If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



            If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

            If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



            If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

            If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



            And so on.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$








            • 4




              $begingroup$
              That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 14:09






            • 6




              $begingroup$
              @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:27






            • 3




              $begingroup$
              Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:29






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:04






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:34















            11












            $begingroup$

            Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



            But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



            If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

            If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



            If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

            If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



            If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

            If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



            And so on.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$








            • 4




              $begingroup$
              That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 14:09






            • 6




              $begingroup$
              @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:27






            • 3




              $begingroup$
              Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:29






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:04






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:34













            11












            11








            11





            $begingroup$

            Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



            But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



            If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

            If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



            If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

            If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



            If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

            If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



            And so on.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$



            Well, I don't like the word "makes" in the question. That implies some sort of causality and causality usually doesn't reverse.



            But you asked for intuition. So, I'd think about some examples, because that seems to spark intuition. Choose one you like:



            If a person is a woman, it is more likely that the person voted for a Democrat.

            If a person voted for a Democrat, it is more likely that the person is a woman.



            If a man is a professional basketball center, it is more likely that he is over 2 meters tall.

            If a man is over 2 meters tall, it is more likely that he is a basketball center.



            If it is over 40 degrees Celsius, it is more likely that there will be a blackout.

            If there has been a blackout, it is more likely that it is over 40 degrees.



            And so on.







            share|cite|improve this answer














            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited Apr 14 at 14:08

























            answered Apr 14 at 11:59









            Peter FlomPeter Flom

            77.6k12110219




            77.6k12110219







            • 4




              $begingroup$
              That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 14:09






            • 6




              $begingroup$
              @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:27






            • 3




              $begingroup$
              Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:29






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:04






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:34












            • 4




              $begingroup$
              That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 14:09






            • 6




              $begingroup$
              @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:27






            • 3




              $begingroup$
              Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
              $endgroup$
              – hobbs
              Apr 14 at 16:29






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:04






            • 7




              $begingroup$
              More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
              $endgroup$
              – Peter Flom
              Apr 14 at 21:34







            4




            4




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 14:09




            $begingroup$
            That's not about probability. That's about 1 to 1 relationships.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 14:09




            6




            6




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            Apr 14 at 16:27




            $begingroup$
            @jww Imagine the statement "if it is raining, the street is wet" (and suppose that's a valid implication for the moment, while the converse is not). Now take a large number of "samples" in different times and places, where you record whether it's raining and whether the street is wet. The street will be wet in more of the samples where it's raining than the samples where it's not; but also, it will be raining in more of the samples where the street is wet than the samples where the street is dry. That's probability.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            Apr 14 at 16:27




            3




            3




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            Apr 14 at 16:29




            $begingroup$
            Both phenomena are caused by the same implication; the implication only works one way, but observing the consequent makes it more likely that you're looking at a sample where the antecedent is true.
            $endgroup$
            – hobbs
            Apr 14 at 16:29




            7




            7




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 21:04




            $begingroup$
            @Barmar Sorry, but that partly demonstrates the correctness of my logic. Because say 36/25,000 is a whole lot higher than 1/150,000,000.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 21:04




            7




            7




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 21:34




            $begingroup$
            More likely than someone who is less than 2 meters tall.
            $endgroup$
            – Peter Flom
            Apr 14 at 21:34











            9












            $begingroup$

            To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
            $$
            eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
            $$

            so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



            But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



            The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$

















              9












              $begingroup$

              To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
              $$
              eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
              $$

              so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



              But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



              The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$















                9












                9








                9





                $begingroup$

                To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
                $$
                eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
                $$

                so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



                But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



                The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.






                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$



                To add on the answer by @Dasherman: What can it mean to say that two events are related, or maybe associated or correlated? Maybe we could for a definition compare the joint probability (Assuming $DeclareMathOperatorPmathbbP P(A)>0, P(B)>0$):
                $$
                eta(A,B)=fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)
                $$

                so if $eta$ is larger than one, $A$ and $B$ occurs together more often than under independence. Then we can say that $A$ and $B$ are positively related.



                But now, using the definition of conditional probability, $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)>1$ is an easy consequence of $P(B mid A) > P(B)$. But $fracP(A cap B)P(A) P(B)$ is completely symmetric in $A$ and $B$ (interchanging all occurrences of the symbol $A$ with $B$ and vice versa) leaves the same formulas, so is also equivalent with $P(A mid B) > P(A)$. That gives the result. So the intuition you ask for is that $eta(A,B)$ is symmetric in $A$ and $B$.



                The answer by @gunes gave a practical example, and it is easy to make others the same way.







                share|cite|improve this answer














                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer








                edited Apr 14 at 15:31

























                answered Apr 14 at 11:49









                kjetil b halvorsenkjetil b halvorsen

                32.5k985241




                32.5k985241





















                    2












                    $begingroup$

                    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                    share|cite|improve this answer











                    $endgroup$








                    • 1




                      $begingroup$
                      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                      $endgroup$
                      – mdewey
                      Apr 14 at 11:16






                    • 2




                      $begingroup$
                      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Dasherman
                      Apr 14 at 12:24
















                    2












                    $begingroup$

                    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                    share|cite|improve this answer











                    $endgroup$








                    • 1




                      $begingroup$
                      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                      $endgroup$
                      – mdewey
                      Apr 14 at 11:16






                    • 2




                      $begingroup$
                      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Dasherman
                      Apr 14 at 12:24














                    2












                    2








                    2





                    $begingroup$

                    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.






                    share|cite|improve this answer











                    $endgroup$



                    If A makes B more likely, this means the events are somehow related. This relation works both ways.



                    If A makes B more likely, this means that A and B tend to happen together. This then means that B also makes A more likely.







                    share|cite|improve this answer














                    share|cite|improve this answer



                    share|cite|improve this answer








                    edited Apr 14 at 12:26

























                    answered Apr 14 at 9:16









                    DashermanDasherman

                    20116




                    20116







                    • 1




                      $begingroup$
                      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                      $endgroup$
                      – mdewey
                      Apr 14 at 11:16






                    • 2




                      $begingroup$
                      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Dasherman
                      Apr 14 at 12:24













                    • 1




                      $begingroup$
                      This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                      $endgroup$
                      – mdewey
                      Apr 14 at 11:16






                    • 2




                      $begingroup$
                      I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Dasherman
                      Apr 14 at 12:24








                    1




                    1




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    Apr 14 at 11:16




                    $begingroup$
                    This perhaps could use some expansion? Without a definition of related it is a bit empty.
                    $endgroup$
                    – mdewey
                    Apr 14 at 11:16




                    2




                    2




                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    Apr 14 at 12:24





                    $begingroup$
                    I was trying to stay away from anything rigorous, since OP asked for an intuitive explanation. You are right that it is quite empty as it is now, but I'm not sure how to expand it in an intuitive way. I have added an attempt.
                    $endgroup$
                    – Dasherman
                    Apr 14 at 12:24












                    2












                    $begingroup$

                    If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                    share|cite|improve this answer











                    $endgroup$

















                      2












                      $begingroup$

                      If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      $endgroup$















                        2












                        2








                        2





                        $begingroup$

                        If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.






                        share|cite|improve this answer











                        $endgroup$



                        If A makes B more likely, A has crucial information that B can infer about itself. Despite the fact that it might not contribute the same amount, that information is not lost the other way around. Eventually, we have two events that their occurrence support each other. I can’t seem to imagine a scenario where occurrence of A increases the likelihood of B, and occurrence of B decreases the likelihood of A. For example, if it rains, the floor will be wet with high probability, and if the floor is wet, it doesn’t mean that it rained but it doesn’t decrease the chances.







                        share|cite|improve this answer














                        share|cite|improve this answer



                        share|cite|improve this answer








                        edited Apr 14 at 14:31

























                        answered Apr 14 at 7:08









                        gunesgunes

                        7,6461316




                        7,6461316





















                            2












                            $begingroup$

                            You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                            $beginarraycc
                            beginarraycc
                            && A & lnot A & \
                            &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                            B& a+b& a & b \
                            lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                            endarray
                            endarray$



                            • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                              B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                              lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                              endarray
                              endarray$$
                              In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                            • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                              B& y& a+z & b-z \
                              lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                              endarray
                              endarray$$



                              You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                              Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                            So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                            If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                            share|cite|improve this answer











                            $endgroup$

















                              2












                              $begingroup$

                              You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                              $beginarraycc
                              beginarraycc
                              && A & lnot A & \
                              &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                              B& a+b& a & b \
                              lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                              endarray
                              endarray$



                              • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$
                                In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                              • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                B& y& a+z & b-z \
                                lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                                endarray
                                endarray$$



                                You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                                Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                              So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                              If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                              share|cite|improve this answer











                              $endgroup$















                                2












                                2








                                2





                                $begingroup$

                                You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                                $beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                                B& a+b& a & b \
                                lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                                endarray
                                endarray$



                                • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                                  beginarraycc
                                  && A & lnot A & \
                                  &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                  B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                                  lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                                  endarray
                                  endarray$$
                                  In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                                • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                                  beginarraycc
                                  && A & lnot A & \
                                  &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                  B& y& a+z & b-z \
                                  lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                                  endarray
                                  endarray$$



                                  You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                                  Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                                So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                                If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.






                                share|cite|improve this answer











                                $endgroup$



                                You can make the math more intuitive by imagining a contingency table.



                                $beginarraycc
                                beginarraycc
                                && A & lnot A & \
                                &a+b+c+d & a+c & b+d \hline
                                B& a+b& a & b \
                                lnot B & c+d& c & d \
                                endarray
                                endarray$



                                • When $A$ and $B$ are independent then the joint probabilities are products of the marginal probabilities $$beginarraycc
                                  beginarraycc
                                  && A & lnot A & \
                                  &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                  B& y& a=xy & b=(1-x)y \
                                  lnot B & 1-y& c=x (1-y) & d=(1-x)(1-y)\
                                  endarray
                                  endarray$$
                                  In such case you would have similar marginal and conditional probabilities, e.g. $P (A) = P (A|B) $ and $P (B)=P (B|A) $.



                                • When there is no independence then you could see this as leaving the parameters $a,b,c,d $ the same (as products of the margins) but with just an adjustment by $pm z $ $$beginarraycc
                                  beginarraycc
                                  && A & lnot A & \
                                  &1 & x & 1-x \hline
                                  B& y& a+z & b-z \
                                  lnot B & 1-y& c-z & d+z\
                                  endarray
                                  endarray$$



                                  You could see this $z$ as breaking the equality of the marginal and conditional probabilities or breaking the relationship for the joint probabilities being products of the marginal probabilities.



                                  Now, from this point of view (of breaking these equalities) you can see that this breaking happens in two ways both for $P(A|B) neq P(A)$ and $P(B|A) neq P(B)$. And the inequality will be for both cases $>$ when $z$ is positive and $<$ when $z $ is negative.



                                So you could see the connection $P(A|B) > P(A)$ then $P(B|A) > P(B)$ via the joint probability $P(B,A) > P (A) P (B) $.



                                If A and B often happen together (joint probability is higher then product of marginal probabilities) then observing the one will make the (conditional) probability of the other higher.







                                share|cite|improve this answer














                                share|cite|improve this answer



                                share|cite|improve this answer








                                edited Apr 14 at 19:17

























                                answered Apr 14 at 18:49









                                Martijn WeteringsMartijn Weterings

                                14.8k2164




                                14.8k2164





















                                    2












                                    $begingroup$

                                    Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                    $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                    Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                    $$Delta(A|B)
                                    = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                    = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                    = fracmathbbP(BmathbbP(B)
                                    = Delta(B|A).$$



                                    The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                    $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                    share|cite|improve this answer









                                    $endgroup$

















                                      2












                                      $begingroup$

                                      Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                      $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                      Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                      $$Delta(A|B)
                                      = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                      = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                      = fracmathbbP(BmathbbP(B)
                                      = Delta(B|A).$$



                                      The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                      $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                      share|cite|improve this answer









                                      $endgroup$















                                        2












                                        2








                                        2





                                        $begingroup$

                                        Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                        $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                        Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                        $$Delta(A|B)
                                        = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                        = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                        = fracmathbbP(BmathbbP(B)
                                        = Delta(B|A).$$



                                        The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                        $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.






                                        share|cite|improve this answer









                                        $endgroup$



                                        Suppose we denote the posterior-to-prior probability ratio of an event as:



                                        $$Delta(A|B) equiv fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)$$



                                        Then an alternative expression of Bayes' theorem (see this related post) is:



                                        $$Delta(A|B)
                                        = fracmathbbP(AmathbbP(A)
                                        = fracmathbbP(A cap B)mathbbP(A) mathbbP(B)
                                        = fracmathbbP(BmathbbP(B)
                                        = Delta(B|A).$$



                                        The posterior-to-prior probability ratio tells us whether the argument event is made more or less likely by the occurrence of the conditioning event (and how much more or less likely). The above form of Bayes' theorem shows use that posterior-to-prior probability ratio is symmetric in the variables.$^dagger$ For example, if observing $B$ makes $A$ more likely than it was a priori, then observing $A$ makes $B$ more likely than it was a priori.




                                        $^dagger$ Note that this is a probability rule, and so it should not be interpreted causally. This symmetry is true in a probabilistic sense for passive observation ---however, it is not true if you intervene in the system to change $A$ or $B$. In that latter case you would need to use causal operations (e.g., the $textdo$ operator) to find the effect of the change in the conditioning variable.







                                        share|cite|improve this answer












                                        share|cite|improve this answer



                                        share|cite|improve this answer










                                        answered Apr 15 at 0:59









                                        BenBen

                                        28.7k233129




                                        28.7k233129





















                                            1












                                            $begingroup$

                                            You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                            You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              Apr 14 at 19:09
















                                            1












                                            $begingroup$

                                            You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                            You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              Apr 14 at 19:09














                                            1












                                            1








                                            1





                                            $begingroup$

                                            You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                            You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$



                                            You are told that Sam is a woman and Kim is a man, and one of the two wears make-up and the other does not. Who of them would you guess wears make-up?



                                            You are told that Sam wears make-up and Kim doesn't, and one of the two is a man and one is a woman. Who would you guess is the woman?







                                            share|cite|improve this answer












                                            share|cite|improve this answer



                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            answered Apr 14 at 16:07









                                            Hagen von EitzenHagen von Eitzen

                                            1413




                                            1413











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              Apr 14 at 19:09

















                                            • $begingroup$
                                              It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              Apr 14 at 19:09
















                                            $begingroup$
                                            It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Martijn Weterings
                                            Apr 14 at 19:09





                                            $begingroup$
                                            It is not so straightforward to connect this to the original problem. What exactly is event A and what is event B? Here it seems more like some comparison of probabilities. Event A is 'x is a women' (not A is the event 'x is a man'). And event B is 'x wears makeup'. But now we suddenly have a Sam and a Kim, where does that come from and should we use anything of information about the subjective masculinity or femininity of their names?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Martijn Weterings
                                            Apr 14 at 19:09












                                            1












                                            $begingroup$

                                            It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                            • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                            The following is not true:



                                            • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                            • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                            However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                            • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                            The following is true:



                                            • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                            • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                            If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                            1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                            Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                            Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                            Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                            If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – H4uZ
                                              2 days ago















                                            1












                                            $begingroup$

                                            It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                            • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                            The following is not true:



                                            • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                            • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                            However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                            • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                            The following is true:



                                            • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                            • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                            If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                            1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                            Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                            Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                            Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                            If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – H4uZ
                                              2 days ago













                                            1












                                            1








                                            1





                                            $begingroup$

                                            It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                            • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                            The following is not true:



                                            • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                            • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                            However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                            • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                            The following is true:



                                            • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                            • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                            If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                            1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                            Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                            Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                            Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                            If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).






                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$



                                            It seems there is some confusion between causation and correlation. Indeed, the question statement is false for causation, as can be seen by an example such as:



                                            • If a dog is wearing a scarf, then it is a domesticated animal.

                                            The following is not true:



                                            • Seeing a domesticated animal wearing a scarf implies it is a dog.

                                            • Seeing a domesticated dog implies it is wearing a scarf.

                                            However, if you are thinking of probabilities (correlation) then it IS true:



                                            • Dogs wearing scarfs are much more likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs (or animals in general for that matter)

                                            The following is true:



                                            • A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal.

                                            • A domesticated dog is more likely to be wearing a scarf than a non-domesticated dog.

                                            If this is not intuitive, think of a pool of animals including ants, dogs and cats. Dogs and cats can both be domesticated and wear scarfs, ants can't neither.



                                            1. If you increase the probability of domesticated animals in your pool, it also will mean you will increase the chance of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            2. If you increase the probability of either cats or dogs, then you will also increase the probability of seeing an animal wearing a scarf.

                                            Being domesticated is the "secret" link between the animal and wearing a scarf, and that "secret" link will exert its influence both ways.



                                            Edit: Giving an example to your question in the comments:



                                            Imagine a world where animals are either Cats or Dogs. They can be either domesticated or not. They can wear a scarf or not. Imagine there exist 100 total animals, 50 Dogs and 50 Cats.



                                            Now consider the statement A to be: "Dogs wearing scarfs are thrice as likely to be a domesticated animal than dogs not wearing scarfs".



                                            If A is not true, then you can imagine that the world could be made of 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs). Same stats for cats.



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) and 40% chance of having a scarf (20/50, 10 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            However, if A is true, then you have a world where there are 50 Dogs, 25 of them domesticated (of which 15 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 5 wear scarfs). Cats maintain the old stats: 50 Cats, 25 of them domesticated (of which 10 wear scarfs), 25 of them wild (of which 10 wear scarfs).



                                            Then, if you saw a domesticated animal in this world, it would have the same 50% chance of being a dog (25/50, 25 dogs out of 50 domesticated animals) but would have 50% (25/50, 15 Dogs and 10 Cats out of 50 domesticated animals).



                                            As you can see, if you say that A is true, then if you saw a domesticated animal wearing a scarf in the world, it would be more likely a Dog (60% or 15/25) than any other animal (in this case Cat, 40% or 10/25).







                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                            share|cite|improve this answer



                                            share|cite|improve this answer








                                            edited 2 days ago





















                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                            answered 2 days ago









                                            H4uZH4uZ

                                            112




                                            112




                                            New contributor




                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.





                                            New contributor





                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            H4uZ is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – H4uZ
                                              2 days ago
















                                            • $begingroup$
                                              This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – H4uZ
                                              2 days ago















                                            $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            2 days ago





                                            $begingroup$
                                            This is the line I have a problem with "A domesticated animal wearing a scarf is more likely to be a dog than another animal." When we made our initial statement we did not make any claim on the other animals that could wear scarfs. There could be 100s. We only made a statement about dogs.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            2 days ago













                                            $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            2 days ago




                                            $begingroup$
                                            See if my edit helps with your particular issue.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – H4uZ
                                            2 days ago











                                            0












                                            $begingroup$

                                            There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                            Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                            If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$








                                            • 5




                                              $begingroup$
                                              This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – wizzwizz4
                                              Apr 14 at 14:31
















                                            0












                                            $begingroup$

                                            There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                            Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                            If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$








                                            • 5




                                              $begingroup$
                                              This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – wizzwizz4
                                              Apr 14 at 14:31














                                            0












                                            0








                                            0





                                            $begingroup$

                                            There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                            Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                            If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$



                                            There is a confusion here between causation and correlation. So I'll give you an example where the exact opposite happens.



                                            Some people are rich, some are poor. Some poor people are given benefits, which makes them less poor. But people who get benefits are still more likely to be poor, even with benefits.



                                            If you are given benefits, that makes it more likely that you can afford cinema tickets. ("Makes it more likely" meaning causality). But if you can afford cinema tickets, that makes it less likely that you are among the people who are poor enough to get benefits, so if you can afford cinema tickets, you are less likely to get benefits.







                                            share|cite|improve this answer












                                            share|cite|improve this answer



                                            share|cite|improve this answer










                                            answered Apr 14 at 14:08









                                            gnasher729gnasher729

                                            48133




                                            48133







                                            • 5




                                              $begingroup$
                                              This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – wizzwizz4
                                              Apr 14 at 14:31













                                            • 5




                                              $begingroup$
                                              This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – wizzwizz4
                                              Apr 14 at 14:31








                                            5




                                            5




                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            Apr 14 at 14:31





                                            $begingroup$
                                            This isn't an answer to the question. Interesting, but not an answer. In fact, it's talking about a different scenario; the reason the opposite happens is that it's using two different metrics that are named similarly (poor without benefits v.s. poor with benefits) and as such is a completely different scenario.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – wizzwizz4
                                            Apr 14 at 14:31












                                            0












                                            $begingroup$

                                            The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                            If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Implication:
                                            A true -> B true
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false


                                            Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                            If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Weak implication:
                                            A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse weak implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                            share|cite|improve this answer








                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rainer P.
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              yesterday















                                            0












                                            $begingroup$

                                            The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                            If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Implication:
                                            A true -> B true
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false


                                            Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                            If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Weak implication:
                                            A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse weak implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                            share|cite|improve this answer








                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$












                                            • $begingroup$
                                              I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rainer P.
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              yesterday













                                            0












                                            0








                                            0





                                            $begingroup$

                                            The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                            If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Implication:
                                            A true -> B true
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false


                                            Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                            If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Weak implication:
                                            A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse weak implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false or (unlikely) true





                                            share|cite|improve this answer








                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            $endgroup$



                                            The intuition becomes clear if you look at the stronger statement:




                                            If A implies B, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Implication:
                                            A true -> B true
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false


                                            Obviously A is more likely to be true if B is known to be true as well, because if B was false then so would be A. The same logic applies to the weaker statement:




                                            If A makes B more likely, then B makes A more likely.




                                            Weak implication:
                                            A true -> B true or (unlikely) false
                                            A false -> B true or false
                                            Reverse weak implication:
                                            B true -> A true or false
                                            B false -> A false or (unlikely) true






                                            share|cite|improve this answer








                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                            share|cite|improve this answer



                                            share|cite|improve this answer






                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.









                                            answered 2 days ago









                                            Rainer P.Rainer P.

                                            101




                                            101




                                            New contributor




                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.





                                            New contributor





                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.






                                            Rainer P. is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                                            Check out our Code of Conduct.











                                            • $begingroup$
                                              I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rainer P.
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              yesterday
















                                            • $begingroup$
                                              I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rahul Deora
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Rainer P.
                                              2 days ago










                                            • $begingroup$
                                              A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                              $endgroup$
                                              – Martijn Weterings
                                              yesterday















                                            $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            2 days ago




                                            $begingroup$
                                            I think what you are saying in the first statement is that in a venn diagram if A is contained in B, then if B is true n(A)/n(B) must be higher than n(A)/n(S) as B is a smaller space than S. Even in the second, you say likewise?
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rahul Deora
                                            2 days ago












                                            $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            2 days ago




                                            $begingroup$
                                            @RahulDeora - Yes, that's how it works. The weak version is much less obvious, but you already did the math anyway. What you asked for is the intuition behind the result, which can be best observed in the stronger statement.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Rainer P.
                                            2 days ago












                                            $begingroup$
                                            A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Martijn Weterings
                                            yesterday




                                            $begingroup$
                                            A small problem with using this statement to gain some more intuition is that it is not entirely true. 'A implying B' is not a sufficient condition for 'when B then A is more likely'. The important distinction is that with 'A implying B' does not need to make B more likely. The most important examples are when B is always true.
                                            $endgroup$
                                            – Martijn Weterings
                                            yesterday











                                            0












                                            $begingroup$

                                            Suppose Alice has a higher free throw rate than average. Then the probability of a shot being successful, given that it's attempted by Alice, is greater than the probability of a shot being successful in general $P(successful|Alice)>P(successful)$. We can also conclude that Alice's share of successful shots is greater than her share of shots in general: $P(Alice|successful)>P(Alice)$.



                                            Or suppose there's a school that has 10% of the students in its school district, but 15% of the straight-A students. Then clearly the percentage of students at that school who are straight-A students is higher than the district-wide percentage.



                                            Another way of looking at it: A is more likely, given B, if $P(A&B)>P(A)P(B)$, and that is completely symmetrical with respect to $A$ and $B$.






                                            share|cite|improve this answer









                                            $endgroup$

















                                              0












                                              $begingroup$

                                              Suppose Alice has a higher free throw rate than average. Then the probability of a shot being successful, given that it's attempted by Alice, is greater than the probability of a shot being successful in general $P(successful|Alice)>P(successful)$. We can also conclude that Alice's share of successful shots is greater than her share of shots in general: $P(Alice|successful)>P(Alice)$.



                                              Or suppose there's a school that has 10% of the students in its school district, but 15% of the straight-A students. Then clearly the percentage of students at that school who are straight-A students is higher than the district-wide percentage.



                                              Another way of looking at it: A is more likely, given B, if $P(A&B)>P(A)P(B)$, and that is completely symmetrical with respect to $A$ and $B$.






                                              share|cite|improve this answer









                                              $endgroup$















                                                0












                                                0








                                                0





                                                $begingroup$

                                                Suppose Alice has a higher free throw rate than average. Then the probability of a shot being successful, given that it's attempted by Alice, is greater than the probability of a shot being successful in general $P(successful|Alice)>P(successful)$. We can also conclude that Alice's share of successful shots is greater than her share of shots in general: $P(Alice|successful)>P(Alice)$.



                                                Or suppose there's a school that has 10% of the students in its school district, but 15% of the straight-A students. Then clearly the percentage of students at that school who are straight-A students is higher than the district-wide percentage.



                                                Another way of looking at it: A is more likely, given B, if $P(A&B)>P(A)P(B)$, and that is completely symmetrical with respect to $A$ and $B$.






                                                share|cite|improve this answer









                                                $endgroup$



                                                Suppose Alice has a higher free throw rate than average. Then the probability of a shot being successful, given that it's attempted by Alice, is greater than the probability of a shot being successful in general $P(successful|Alice)>P(successful)$. We can also conclude that Alice's share of successful shots is greater than her share of shots in general: $P(Alice|successful)>P(Alice)$.



                                                Or suppose there's a school that has 10% of the students in its school district, but 15% of the straight-A students. Then clearly the percentage of students at that school who are straight-A students is higher than the district-wide percentage.



                                                Another way of looking at it: A is more likely, given B, if $P(A&B)>P(A)P(B)$, and that is completely symmetrical with respect to $A$ and $B$.







                                                share|cite|improve this answer












                                                share|cite|improve this answer



                                                share|cite|improve this answer










                                                answered 2 days ago









                                                AcccumulationAcccumulation

                                                1,69626




                                                1,69626















                                                    protected by gung 2 days ago



                                                    Thank you for your interest in this question.
                                                    Because it has attracted low-quality or spam answers that had to be removed, posting an answer now requires 10 reputation on this site (the association bonus does not count).



                                                    Would you like to answer one of these unanswered questions instead?



                                                    Popular posts from this blog

                                                    Category:9 (number) SubcategoriesMedia in category "9 (number)"Navigation menuUpload mediaGND ID: 4485639-8Library of Congress authority ID: sh85091979ReasonatorScholiaStatistics

                                                    Circuit construction for execution of conditional statements using least significant bitHow are two different registers being used as “control”?How exactly is the stated composite state of the two registers being produced using the $R_zz$ controlled rotations?Efficiently performing controlled rotations in HHLWould this quantum algorithm implementation work?How to prepare a superposed states of odd integers from $1$ to $sqrtN$?Why is this implementation of the order finding algorithm not working?Circuit construction for Hamiltonian simulationHow can I invert the least significant bit of a certain term of a superposed state?Implementing an oracleImplementing a controlled sum operation

                                                    Magento 2 “No Payment Methods” in Admin New OrderHow to integrate Paypal Express Checkout with the Magento APIMagento 1.5 - Sales > Order > edit order and shipping methods disappearAuto Invoice Check/Money Order Payment methodAdd more simple payment methods?Shipping methods not showingWhat should I do to change payment methods if changing the configuration has no effects?1.9 - No Payment Methods showing upMy Payment Methods not Showing for downloadable/virtual product when checkout?Magento2 API to access internal payment methodHow to call an existing payment methods in the registration form?