Tricategorical coherenceLax Functors and Equivalence of Bicategories?Effects of “weak” vs. “strict” categories in Eckmann-Hilton argumentsCan equivalences be strictified to isomorphisms?Simple-minded coherence of tricategoriesAbout the definition of lax.functor between tricategoriesIs the theory of weak $n$-categories a cofibrant replacement of the theory of strict ones?Are strict $infty$-categories localized at weak equivalences a full subcategory of weak $infty$-categories?Weak complicial sets: Are the morphisms too strict?Is there an “injective version” of the Bergner model structure?Coherence theorem for tetracategories, weak $n$-categories

Tricategorical coherence


Lax Functors and Equivalence of Bicategories?Effects of “weak” vs. “strict” categories in Eckmann-Hilton argumentsCan equivalences be strictified to isomorphisms?Simple-minded coherence of tricategoriesAbout the definition of lax.functor between tricategoriesIs the theory of weak $n$-categories a cofibrant replacement of the theory of strict ones?Are strict $infty$-categories localized at weak equivalences a full subcategory of weak $infty$-categories?Weak complicial sets: Are the morphisms too strict?Is there an “injective version” of the Bergner model structure?Coherence theorem for tetracategories, weak $n$-categories













6












$begingroup$


Why does coherence begin to matter at the tricategorical level?



It is well known that every weak $2$-category is equivalent to a strict $2$-category, with the equivalence essentially given by (unless I'm mistaken) the $2$-Yoneda embedding for an arbitrary $2$-category into its strict $2$-category of $2$-presheaves into $mathfrakCat$ -- this means we can effectively ignore the coherence diagrams for associativity and unitarity in $2$-categories and work with strict ones where composition is associative on the nose and units vanish under composition.



This is not so for $3$-categories; Gordon, Power and Street proved that all weak $3$-categories are equivalent to Gray categories, where associativity and unitarity still hold on the nose, but we have an additional coherence notion in play called 'interchange' for $2$-morphisms which introduces fundamental differences between $3$-categories with strict interchange and weak interchange laws.




Intuitively speaking, why does this type of coherence 'matter' more than the associative and unital coherence that appears at the $2$-categorical level?




The notions of '$n$-equivalence' become more varied as we move into higher $n$ as I understand it, so perhaps the 'correct' notion of $3$-equivalence is sensitive to interchange in some way that $2$-equivalence isn't sensitive to associativity for $1$-cells?



I am currently working through the linked Gordon-Power-Street paper on coherence for tricategories and suspect the answer is buried in their proof of the tricategorical coherence theorem, but I thought someone here might already be familiar with it and able to help a newcomer -- any assistance is appreciated.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter May
    Jul 8 at 14:37










  • $begingroup$
    @PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 14:59















6












$begingroup$


Why does coherence begin to matter at the tricategorical level?



It is well known that every weak $2$-category is equivalent to a strict $2$-category, with the equivalence essentially given by (unless I'm mistaken) the $2$-Yoneda embedding for an arbitrary $2$-category into its strict $2$-category of $2$-presheaves into $mathfrakCat$ -- this means we can effectively ignore the coherence diagrams for associativity and unitarity in $2$-categories and work with strict ones where composition is associative on the nose and units vanish under composition.



This is not so for $3$-categories; Gordon, Power and Street proved that all weak $3$-categories are equivalent to Gray categories, where associativity and unitarity still hold on the nose, but we have an additional coherence notion in play called 'interchange' for $2$-morphisms which introduces fundamental differences between $3$-categories with strict interchange and weak interchange laws.




Intuitively speaking, why does this type of coherence 'matter' more than the associative and unital coherence that appears at the $2$-categorical level?




The notions of '$n$-equivalence' become more varied as we move into higher $n$ as I understand it, so perhaps the 'correct' notion of $3$-equivalence is sensitive to interchange in some way that $2$-equivalence isn't sensitive to associativity for $1$-cells?



I am currently working through the linked Gordon-Power-Street paper on coherence for tricategories and suspect the answer is buried in their proof of the tricategorical coherence theorem, but I thought someone here might already be familiar with it and able to help a newcomer -- any assistance is appreciated.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter May
    Jul 8 at 14:37










  • $begingroup$
    @PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 14:59













6












6








6


1



$begingroup$


Why does coherence begin to matter at the tricategorical level?



It is well known that every weak $2$-category is equivalent to a strict $2$-category, with the equivalence essentially given by (unless I'm mistaken) the $2$-Yoneda embedding for an arbitrary $2$-category into its strict $2$-category of $2$-presheaves into $mathfrakCat$ -- this means we can effectively ignore the coherence diagrams for associativity and unitarity in $2$-categories and work with strict ones where composition is associative on the nose and units vanish under composition.



This is not so for $3$-categories; Gordon, Power and Street proved that all weak $3$-categories are equivalent to Gray categories, where associativity and unitarity still hold on the nose, but we have an additional coherence notion in play called 'interchange' for $2$-morphisms which introduces fundamental differences between $3$-categories with strict interchange and weak interchange laws.




Intuitively speaking, why does this type of coherence 'matter' more than the associative and unital coherence that appears at the $2$-categorical level?




The notions of '$n$-equivalence' become more varied as we move into higher $n$ as I understand it, so perhaps the 'correct' notion of $3$-equivalence is sensitive to interchange in some way that $2$-equivalence isn't sensitive to associativity for $1$-cells?



I am currently working through the linked Gordon-Power-Street paper on coherence for tricategories and suspect the answer is buried in their proof of the tricategorical coherence theorem, but I thought someone here might already be familiar with it and able to help a newcomer -- any assistance is appreciated.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




Why does coherence begin to matter at the tricategorical level?



It is well known that every weak $2$-category is equivalent to a strict $2$-category, with the equivalence essentially given by (unless I'm mistaken) the $2$-Yoneda embedding for an arbitrary $2$-category into its strict $2$-category of $2$-presheaves into $mathfrakCat$ -- this means we can effectively ignore the coherence diagrams for associativity and unitarity in $2$-categories and work with strict ones where composition is associative on the nose and units vanish under composition.



This is not so for $3$-categories; Gordon, Power and Street proved that all weak $3$-categories are equivalent to Gray categories, where associativity and unitarity still hold on the nose, but we have an additional coherence notion in play called 'interchange' for $2$-morphisms which introduces fundamental differences between $3$-categories with strict interchange and weak interchange laws.




Intuitively speaking, why does this type of coherence 'matter' more than the associative and unital coherence that appears at the $2$-categorical level?




The notions of '$n$-equivalence' become more varied as we move into higher $n$ as I understand it, so perhaps the 'correct' notion of $3$-equivalence is sensitive to interchange in some way that $2$-equivalence isn't sensitive to associativity for $1$-cells?



I am currently working through the linked Gordon-Power-Street paper on coherence for tricategories and suspect the answer is buried in their proof of the tricategorical coherence theorem, but I thought someone here might already be familiar with it and able to help a newcomer -- any assistance is appreciated.







ct.category-theory higher-category-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jul 8 at 6:03









Alec RheaAlec Rhea

1,6111 gold badge12 silver badges23 bronze badges




1,6111 gold badge12 silver badges23 bronze badges







  • 1




    $begingroup$
    You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter May
    Jul 8 at 14:37










  • $begingroup$
    @PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 14:59












  • 1




    $begingroup$
    You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
    $endgroup$
    – Peter May
    Jul 8 at 14:37










  • $begingroup$
    @PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 14:59







1




1




$begingroup$
You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
$endgroup$
– Peter May
Jul 8 at 14:37




$begingroup$
You may want to look at Nick Gurski's fully algebraic treatment of coherence in tricategories ``Coherence in three-dimensional category theory''.
$endgroup$
– Peter May
Jul 8 at 14:37












$begingroup$
@PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
$endgroup$
– Alec Rhea
Jul 8 at 14:59




$begingroup$
@PeterMayThat looks very relevant, muchas gracias.
$endgroup$
– Alec Rhea
Jul 8 at 14:59










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















5












$begingroup$

The short answer is that what matters is the combination of strict interchange and strict units, because interchange and units are what go into the Eckmann-Hilton argument, and dimension 3 is the first dimension in which you can have weak commutativity (e.g. braided monoidal categories are degenerate tricategories). GPS choose to strictify the units and therefore not the interchange, but you can also choose to strictify the interchange and not the units:




André Joyal, Joachim Kock, Weak units and homotopy 3-types, in: Street Festschrift: Categories in algebra, geometry and mathematical physics, Contemp. Math 431 (2007), 257-276, doi:10.1090/conm/431/08277, arXiv:math/0602084.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Much appreciated!
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 6:59













Your Answer








StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "504"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f335672%2ftricategorical-coherence%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









5












$begingroup$

The short answer is that what matters is the combination of strict interchange and strict units, because interchange and units are what go into the Eckmann-Hilton argument, and dimension 3 is the first dimension in which you can have weak commutativity (e.g. braided monoidal categories are degenerate tricategories). GPS choose to strictify the units and therefore not the interchange, but you can also choose to strictify the interchange and not the units:




André Joyal, Joachim Kock, Weak units and homotopy 3-types, in: Street Festschrift: Categories in algebra, geometry and mathematical physics, Contemp. Math 431 (2007), 257-276, doi:10.1090/conm/431/08277, arXiv:math/0602084.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Much appreciated!
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 6:59















5












$begingroup$

The short answer is that what matters is the combination of strict interchange and strict units, because interchange and units are what go into the Eckmann-Hilton argument, and dimension 3 is the first dimension in which you can have weak commutativity (e.g. braided monoidal categories are degenerate tricategories). GPS choose to strictify the units and therefore not the interchange, but you can also choose to strictify the interchange and not the units:




André Joyal, Joachim Kock, Weak units and homotopy 3-types, in: Street Festschrift: Categories in algebra, geometry and mathematical physics, Contemp. Math 431 (2007), 257-276, doi:10.1090/conm/431/08277, arXiv:math/0602084.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    Much appreciated!
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 6:59













5












5








5





$begingroup$

The short answer is that what matters is the combination of strict interchange and strict units, because interchange and units are what go into the Eckmann-Hilton argument, and dimension 3 is the first dimension in which you can have weak commutativity (e.g. braided monoidal categories are degenerate tricategories). GPS choose to strictify the units and therefore not the interchange, but you can also choose to strictify the interchange and not the units:




André Joyal, Joachim Kock, Weak units and homotopy 3-types, in: Street Festschrift: Categories in algebra, geometry and mathematical physics, Contemp. Math 431 (2007), 257-276, doi:10.1090/conm/431/08277, arXiv:math/0602084.







share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



The short answer is that what matters is the combination of strict interchange and strict units, because interchange and units are what go into the Eckmann-Hilton argument, and dimension 3 is the first dimension in which you can have weak commutativity (e.g. braided monoidal categories are degenerate tricategories). GPS choose to strictify the units and therefore not the interchange, but you can also choose to strictify the interchange and not the units:




André Joyal, Joachim Kock, Weak units and homotopy 3-types, in: Street Festschrift: Categories in algebra, geometry and mathematical physics, Contemp. Math 431 (2007), 257-276, doi:10.1090/conm/431/08277, arXiv:math/0602084.








share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Jul 8 at 7:17









David Roberts

18.2k4 gold badges64 silver badges188 bronze badges




18.2k4 gold badges64 silver badges188 bronze badges










answered Jul 8 at 6:15









Mike ShulmanMike Shulman

39k4 gold badges90 silver badges240 bronze badges




39k4 gold badges90 silver badges240 bronze badges











  • $begingroup$
    Much appreciated!
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 6:59
















  • $begingroup$
    Much appreciated!
    $endgroup$
    – Alec Rhea
    Jul 8 at 6:59















$begingroup$
Much appreciated!
$endgroup$
– Alec Rhea
Jul 8 at 6:59




$begingroup$
Much appreciated!
$endgroup$
– Alec Rhea
Jul 8 at 6:59

















draft saved

draft discarded
















































Thanks for contributing an answer to MathOverflow!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid


  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f335672%2ftricategorical-coherence%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Category:9 (number) SubcategoriesMedia in category "9 (number)"Navigation menuUpload mediaGND ID: 4485639-8Library of Congress authority ID: sh85091979ReasonatorScholiaStatistics

Circuit construction for execution of conditional statements using least significant bitHow are two different registers being used as “control”?How exactly is the stated composite state of the two registers being produced using the $R_zz$ controlled rotations?Efficiently performing controlled rotations in HHLWould this quantum algorithm implementation work?How to prepare a superposed states of odd integers from $1$ to $sqrtN$?Why is this implementation of the order finding algorithm not working?Circuit construction for Hamiltonian simulationHow can I invert the least significant bit of a certain term of a superposed state?Implementing an oracleImplementing a controlled sum operation

Magento 2 “No Payment Methods” in Admin New OrderHow to integrate Paypal Express Checkout with the Magento APIMagento 1.5 - Sales > Order > edit order and shipping methods disappearAuto Invoice Check/Money Order Payment methodAdd more simple payment methods?Shipping methods not showingWhat should I do to change payment methods if changing the configuration has no effects?1.9 - No Payment Methods showing upMy Payment Methods not Showing for downloadable/virtual product when checkout?Magento2 API to access internal payment methodHow to call an existing payment methods in the registration form?