Why does the 'metric Lagrangian' approach appear to fail in Newtonian mechanics?Deriving the Lagrangian for a free particleLagrangian for relativistic massless point particleCurved spacetime point particle Lagrangian densityConfusion regarding the principle of least action in Landau & Lifshitz “The Classical Theory of Fields”Is there a Maupertuis principle for General Relativity?When the equations of motion are not unique (eg. when they are given by eigenvectors), which will the free particle adhere to?Physical motivation for Lagrangian formalismAre there arguments for the form of the Lagrangian in classical mechanics?Schwinger's variation of the action of point particle with *both* time and position as independent variablesDeriving the geodesic equation using a Lagrange multiplier to fix affine parametrisationWhy the Lagrangian of a free particle cannot depend on the position or time, explicitly?Confusing with the equation $(2.4)$ and $(2.5)$ of Landau and Lifshitz, Mechanics, Chapter 1, The principle of Least Action
Why is the relationship between frequency and pitch exponential?
Old black and white movie: glowing black rocks slowly turn you into stone upon touch
Could the Missouri River be running while Lake Michigan was frozen several meters deep?
1980s (or earlier) book where people live a long time but they have short memories
Why is c4 bad when playing the London against a King's Indian?
I wrote a scene that the majority of my readers loved. How do I get back to that place while writing my new book?
Accidentally cashed a check twice
What do we gain with higher order logics?
Credit card offering 0.5 miles for every cent rounded up. Too good to be true?
Opposite of "Squeaky wheel gets the grease"
Company is asking me to work from overseas, but wants me to take a paycut
If Boris Johnson were prosecuted and convicted of lying about Brexit, can that be used to cancel Brexit?
Convert camelCase and PascalCase to Title Case
How to pass a regex when finding a directory path in bash?
What is the right way to float a home lab?
Building a road to escape Earth's gravity by making a pyramid on Antartica
What are they doing to this poor rocket?
Diet Coke or water?
Chopin: marche funèbre bar 15 impossible place
Who operates delivery flights for commercial airlines?
California: "For quality assurance, this phone call is being recorded"
How do you build a story from a world?
What's the logic behind the the organization of Hamburg's bus transport into "rings"?
Prove that a function is indefinitely differentiable
Why does the 'metric Lagrangian' approach appear to fail in Newtonian mechanics?
Deriving the Lagrangian for a free particleLagrangian for relativistic massless point particleCurved spacetime point particle Lagrangian densityConfusion regarding the principle of least action in Landau & Lifshitz “The Classical Theory of Fields”Is there a Maupertuis principle for General Relativity?When the equations of motion are not unique (eg. when they are given by eigenvectors), which will the free particle adhere to?Physical motivation for Lagrangian formalismAre there arguments for the form of the Lagrangian in classical mechanics?Schwinger's variation of the action of point particle with *both* time and position as independent variablesDeriving the geodesic equation using a Lagrange multiplier to fix affine parametrisationWhy the Lagrangian of a free particle cannot depend on the position or time, explicitly?Confusing with the equation $(2.4)$ and $(2.5)$ of Landau and Lifshitz, Mechanics, Chapter 1, The principle of Least Action
$begingroup$
A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:
The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
path parameterThe action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)- 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:
$$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$
The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.
In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.
The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$- Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$ - We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
$$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$
This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
$$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
$$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
$$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!
Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.
Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....
special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action
New contributor
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:
The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
path parameterThe action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)- 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:
$$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$
The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.
In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.
The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$- Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$ - We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
$$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$
This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
$$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
$$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
$$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!
Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.
Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....
special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action
New contributor
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:
The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
path parameterThe action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)- 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:
$$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$
The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.
In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.
The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$- Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$ - We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
$$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$
This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
$$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
$$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
$$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!
Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.
Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....
special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action
New contributor
$endgroup$
A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:
The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
path parameterThe action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)- 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:
$$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$
The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.
In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.
The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$- Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
$$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$ - We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
$$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$
This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
$$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
$$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
$$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!
Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.
Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....
special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action
special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action
New contributor
New contributor
edited May 27 at 18:56
almightyjack
New contributor
asked May 26 at 11:15
almightyjackalmightyjack
464
464
New contributor
New contributor
add a comment |
add a comment |
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
$$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.
Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
$$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
$$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.
We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "151"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);
else
createEditor();
);
function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: false,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: null,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);
);
almightyjack is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f482512%2fwhy-does-the-metric-lagrangian-approach-appear-to-fail-in-newtonian-mechanics%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
$$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.
Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
$$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
$$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
$$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.
Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
$$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
$$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
$$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.
Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
$$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
$$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.
$endgroup$
The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
$$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.
Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
$$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
$$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.
answered May 26 at 11:39
knzhouknzhou
49.9k12137245
49.9k12137245
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
$begingroup$
I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 12:51
1
1
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
@almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
May 26 at 12:59
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
$endgroup$
– almightyjack
May 26 at 13:10
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
$begingroup$
@knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
$endgroup$
– The_Sympathizer
May 27 at 0:15
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.
We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.
We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.
We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.
$endgroup$
A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.
We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.
edited May 26 at 21:35
answered May 26 at 12:24
Qmechanic♦Qmechanic
109k122081281
109k122081281
add a comment |
add a comment |
almightyjack is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
almightyjack is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
almightyjack is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
almightyjack is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
Thanks for contributing an answer to Physics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f482512%2fwhy-does-the-metric-lagrangian-approach-appear-to-fail-in-newtonian-mechanics%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown